01.10.2014 Views

An Introduction to Critical Thinking and Creativity - always yours

An Introduction to Critical Thinking and Creativity - always yours

An Introduction to Critical Thinking and Creativity - always yours

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

EVALUATING ANALOGICAL ARGUMENTS 197<br />

erties that support the conclusion. This is perhaps the most important part of analogical<br />

reasoning because it helps us underst<strong>and</strong> why an analogy is supposed <strong>to</strong><br />

work. The argument must highlight important aspects of similarity, if the analogy<br />

plays any role at all in supporting the conclusion. Then you can start evaluating<br />

the argument, using the principles below.<br />

21.1 EVALUATING ANALOGICAL ARGUMENTS<br />

There is no mechanical method for evaluating analogical arguments, but here is a<br />

checklist of the main criteria:<br />

• Truth: Are the two things really similar in the way described? Obviously, an<br />

argument is not acceptable if it has a false premise. In the third argument<br />

above, if it turns out that you do not like outdoor activities <strong>and</strong> much prefer<br />

sleeping in bed, then you are not like my friend <strong>and</strong> the argument should be<br />

rejected.<br />

• Relevance: Are the shared properties relevant <strong>to</strong> the conclusion? Even when<br />

the source <strong>and</strong> target are similar, the properties they share must be relevant<br />

<strong>to</strong> the conclusion for the analogical argument <strong>to</strong> be acceptable. In other<br />

words, having the shared properties increases the probability of having the<br />

inferred property. To use a concrete example, suppose we change the third<br />

argument above slightly:<br />

You are just like my friend since you both like <strong>to</strong> eat chocolates.<br />

My friend likes rock climbing.<br />

You will also like rock climbing.<br />

This is clearly a lousy argument, even if the premises are true. A preference<br />

for chocolate does not make a person more likely <strong>to</strong> enjoy rock climbing. In<br />

other words, the common property is simply irrelevant <strong>to</strong> the inferred property.<br />

Notice that we need <strong>to</strong> use our commonsense <strong>and</strong> background knowledge<br />

<strong>to</strong> determine relevance. It is not enough <strong>to</strong> focus on the argument<br />

only. For example, if scientists discover that the majority of people who<br />

like chocolates actually enjoy rock climbing, then our background knowledge<br />

has changed, <strong>and</strong> this argument would become more convincing. This<br />

shows that analogical reasoning is typically a kind of inductive reasoning.<br />

• Number <strong>and</strong> diversity: Are there many shared properties of different types?<br />

The strength of an analogical argument depends not just on the relevance<br />

of the shared property. The number of shared properties makes a difference<br />

also. If both you <strong>and</strong> my friend enjoy outdoor activities, <strong>and</strong> in addition you<br />

are both agile, with good physical strength <strong>and</strong> balance, then it is more likely<br />

that you will like rock climbing. In short, finding more relevant properties<br />

shared by the source <strong>and</strong> the target can strengthen an analogical argument.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!