26.04.2018 Views

Abdal Hakim Murad - The Cambridge Companion to Islamic Theology

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

God: essence and attributes 133<br />

To show their ‘‘incoherence’’, Ghazalı summarises their arguments<br />

as follows. If an attribute and that <strong>to</strong> which it is attributed are not the<br />

same, then each one will dispense with the other, or each one will need<br />

the other for it <strong>to</strong> be, or one will dispense with the other while the other<br />

will be in need of the former. In the first of these cases, both will be<br />

necessary existents due <strong>to</strong> themselves, and this is implausible. In the<br />

case where each one of them needs the other, then neither is a<br />

‘‘Necessary-Existent-due-<strong>to</strong>-Itself’’, and this is impossible in the case of<br />

the divine. However, if one has no need of the other, but is needed by it,<br />

then one of them acts as the cause of the other. So in this case, if what is<br />

ascribed with an attribute is in need of it, the one in need is characterised<br />

by a lack, and this does not apply <strong>to</strong> the divine. 26 Ghazalı’s reply <strong>to</strong> these<br />

speculations is that the essence of the Necessary Existent is eternal<br />

without agents, and so are His attributes. 27 He also objects <strong>to</strong> the<br />

falasifa’s claim that the affirmation of the attributes entails that the<br />

First Principle cannot be absolutely self-sufficient, given that since<br />

the First does not need anything other than Himself, therefore He would<br />

not need the attributes. Ghazalı thinks that these philosophical<br />

sophistications are part of a mere ‘‘rhe<strong>to</strong>rical preaching that is extremely<br />

feeble’’. After all, he asserts that ‘‘the attributes of perfection are not<br />

separate from the essence of the Perfect, so as <strong>to</strong> say that He is in need of<br />

another’’. Like Ash‘arı, he holds that the attributes are not reduced <strong>to</strong><br />

the essence itself while being coeternal with it without cause. When the<br />

philosophers affirm that God is a knower, they face the problem of<br />

admitting that there is something superadded <strong>to</strong> the essence, namely<br />

knowledge.<br />

Most adherents of falsafa hold that God knows only Himself.<br />

However, Avicenna argues that God knows Himself as well as knowing<br />

everything else in a universal manner, given that the knowledge of<br />

particulars implies change in the divine essence. In response, Ghazalı<br />

asks whether God’s knowledge of Himself is identical with His knowledge<br />

of all genera and species. If the philosophers reply that His<br />

knowledge of Himself is indeed identical with His knowledge of<br />

everything else, then their position is untenable. If they say that they are<br />

not identical, then multiplicity is implied. Neither reply convinces.<br />

Furthermore, it cannot be the case that God would know only Himself<br />

given the scriptural affirmation that ‘‘not even the weight of an a<strong>to</strong>m in<br />

the heavens or the earth escapes His knowledge’’ (10:61). Unlike other<br />

philosophers, Avicenna is ‘‘ashamed’’ of asserting that God knows only<br />

Himself and does not know anything else, given that this implies deficiency.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, in avoiding assertions that might imply change or<br />

<strong>Cambridge</strong> Collections Online © <strong>Cambridge</strong> University Press, 2008

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!