26.04.2018 Views

Abdal Hakim Murad - The Cambridge Companion to Islamic Theology

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>The</strong> existence of God 209<br />

Arguments from particularisation<br />

This is the main form of argument used by early Ash‘arites, and is<br />

often used by Mu‘tazilites and later Ash‘arites. It turns on the notion of<br />

particularisation (takhs _<br />

ıs _<br />

), which has its background in a trend distinctly<br />

characteristic of classical kalam, stemming from the sense that<br />

randomness of any kind, in either quantity or quality, is inconceivable.<br />

Every seemingly random fact about the world or things therein thus calls<br />

for explanation. Different instances of this type of proof cite different<br />

facts. <strong>The</strong> earliest arguments were relatively simple and departed from<br />

the a<strong>to</strong>mist framework of classical kalam, as in the following two<br />

arguments advanced by the Ash‘arite theologian al-Baqillanı (d.1013).<br />

He argues that we observe identical things coming in<strong>to</strong> being at<br />

different times. If the occurrence of one thing at a particular moment is<br />

due <strong>to</strong> an intrinsic quality thereof, all similar things should occur at the<br />

same time. It thus appears that nothing intrinsic <strong>to</strong> the thing itself could<br />

make it more likely <strong>to</strong> occur at a particular moment rather than at<br />

another moment, or more likely <strong>to</strong> occur at a given moment than<br />

another, similar thing. <strong>The</strong>refore, there must be an external voluntary<br />

effecter, who causes particular things <strong>to</strong> occur at particular moments.<br />

Baqillanı further argues that objects in this world have different<br />

shapes, since they consist of different arrangements of a<strong>to</strong>ms. Yet it is<br />

conceivable for each object <strong>to</strong> have an arrangement different from the<br />

one it actually has:<br />

What is square can be round, and what is round square. What has the<br />

shape of one particular animal can have that of another. Each object<br />

may lose its shape <strong>to</strong> take on a different shape. It is inconceivable<br />

that what has a certain particular shape will have it by virtue of<br />

itself, or because it is possible for it <strong>to</strong> have it. Otherwise, if [the<br />

latter] were the case, [the object] would have <strong>to</strong> take on every shape<br />

that it may possibly take, all at the same time, so that it would<br />

acquire all dissimilar shapes simultaneously. 46<br />

<strong>The</strong> absurdity of this, Baqillanı continues, proves that the shapes of<br />

objects must have been determined by a ‘‘shaper’’, possessed of will.<br />

Both arguments are occasionalistic and presuppose classical<br />

Ash‘arite a<strong>to</strong>mism and a rejection of natural causality. Things, we are<br />

<strong>to</strong>ld, do not come in<strong>to</strong> being at particular moments with particular<br />

characteristics because of any natural fac<strong>to</strong>rs, such as intrinsic properties<br />

therein or a causal nexus between one moment and another. <strong>The</strong>re<br />

is no natural necessity determining the way things actually are. All<br />

things, rather, consist of identical a<strong>to</strong>ms and of different accidents<br />

<strong>Cambridge</strong> Collections Online © <strong>Cambridge</strong> University Press, 2008

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!