26.04.2018 Views

Abdal Hakim Murad - The Cambridge Companion to Islamic Theology

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

212 Ayman Shihadeh<br />

Avicenna claims <strong>to</strong> advance a purely metaphysical proof (as opposed<br />

<strong>to</strong> a physical proof), one that rests purely on an analysis of the notion of<br />

existence qua existence, without consideration of any attributes of the<br />

physical world. 53 He writes:<br />

Reflect on how our proof for the existence and oneness of the First<br />

and His being free from attributes did not require reflection on<br />

anything except existence itself and how it did not require any<br />

consideration of His creation and acting even though the latter<br />

[provide] evidential proof for Him.<br />

This mode, however, is more reliable and noble, that is, where<br />

when we consider the state of existence, we find that existence<br />

inasmuch as it is existence bears witness <strong>to</strong> Him, while He<br />

thereafter bears witness <strong>to</strong> all that comes after Him in existence. 54<br />

If true, this characterisation would set the proof apart from all<br />

contemporaneous, cosmological and teleological proofs. In contemporary<br />

terminology, it would qualify it <strong>to</strong> be an on<strong>to</strong>logical proof, that is <strong>to</strong><br />

say, a proof which argues for the existence of God entirely from a priori<br />

premises and makes no use of any premises that derive from our<br />

observation of the world. Recent studies of Avicenna’s proof, however,<br />

differ on whether the argument is cosmological or indeed on<strong>to</strong>logical. 55<br />

As we will see, doubt with regard <strong>to</strong> the purported fundamental novelty<br />

of Avicenna’s proof was expressed centuries ago.<br />

<strong>The</strong> proof rests on conceptions that, Avicenna contends, are primary<br />

in the mind, intuited without need of sensory perception and mental<br />

cogitation, namely ‘‘the existent’’ and ‘‘the necessary’’. <strong>The</strong> conception<br />

‘‘the possible’’, being what is neither necessary nor impossible, is either<br />

equally primary, or derived directly from the conception ‘‘the necessary’’.<br />

An existent, by virtue of itself, is either possibly existent, or<br />

necessarily existent. If we posit an existent that is necessary in itself,<br />

then, Avicenna argues, it will have <strong>to</strong> be uncaused, absolutely simple,<br />

one and unique. If we posit an existent that is possible in itself, it will<br />

have <strong>to</strong> depend for its existence on another existent. <strong>The</strong> latter will be its<br />

cause, not in the sense of being an antecedent accidental cause for its<br />

temporal generation, but as a coexistent essential cause for its continuous<br />

existence. If this cause is itself a possible existent, it will have <strong>to</strong><br />

exist by virtue of another. <strong>The</strong> series of actual existents, Avicenna<br />

argues, cannot continue ad infinitum, but must terminate in an<br />

uncaused existent that is necessary in itself.<br />

But why does a possible existent require a cause <strong>to</strong> exist? Avicenna<br />

proves this using the argument from particularisation, apparently<br />

<strong>Cambridge</strong> Collections Online © <strong>Cambridge</strong> University Press, 2008

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!