22.01.2013 Views

Rudolf Steiner's Vision for the Future - Anthroposophical Society in ...

Rudolf Steiner's Vision for the Future - Anthroposophical Society in ...

Rudolf Steiner's Vision for the Future - Anthroposophical Society in ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Like o<strong>the</strong>r commentators, Tantillo starts with Goe<strong>the</strong>’s<br />

objections to reduc<strong>in</strong>g nature to its quantifiable aspects,<br />

ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stead that nature is best understood not<br />

through controlled experiments, but through a multiplicity<br />

of perspectives. She emphasizes Goe<strong>the</strong>’s distrust of ma<strong>the</strong>matics<br />

and his <strong>in</strong>sistence that scientists need cont<strong>in</strong>ually to<br />

assess <strong>the</strong>ir own possible prejudices <strong>in</strong> relation to <strong>the</strong>ir object<br />

of study. To understand nature truly and study it effectively,<br />

<strong>the</strong> scientist should fashion a method out of nature’s own<br />

procedures and learn to be “as quick and mobile” as nature<br />

itself.<br />

Each of <strong>the</strong> four pr<strong>in</strong>ciples she <strong>in</strong>vestigates describes “nature’s<br />

will to create, evolve, struggle, trans<strong>for</strong>m, and metamorphose.”<br />

Her goal is to show how Goe<strong>the</strong> uses his<br />

scientific pr<strong>in</strong>ciples not to reduce nature to fixed laws but,<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r, to describe from multiple po<strong>in</strong>ts of view how nature<br />

not only creates laws <strong>for</strong> itself, but also oversteps those laws<br />

to <strong>for</strong>m new ones. An underly<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>me of Tantillo’s study<br />

is <strong>the</strong> degree to which Goe<strong>the</strong>’s observations can be seen as<br />

evolutionary <strong>in</strong> character, and she susta<strong>in</strong>s a runn<strong>in</strong>g dialogue<br />

with o<strong>the</strong>r writers on Goe<strong>the</strong> who have ei<strong>the</strong>r argued <strong>for</strong> or<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>st his be<strong>in</strong>g a <strong>for</strong>erunner of Darw<strong>in</strong>. She articulates one<br />

of <strong>the</strong> great strengths of <strong>the</strong> Goe<strong>the</strong>an perspective, and why<br />

one might look to him <strong>for</strong> help with present issues <strong>in</strong> science:<br />

“While scholars have discussed whe<strong>the</strong>r and to what extent<br />

Goe<strong>the</strong> believed <strong>in</strong> descent, <strong>the</strong> more central question <strong>for</strong><br />

Goe<strong>the</strong>’s science may well not be how <strong>the</strong> process of evolution<br />

occurs, but why it occurs” (110). Her rich and full account<br />

of his thought gives weight to his answer: that<br />

evolution results from nature’s own creativity and striv<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

One of <strong>the</strong> chief dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g features of Goe<strong>the</strong>’s science<br />

is his refusal to elim<strong>in</strong>ate aes<strong>the</strong>tic and moral dimensions<br />

from <strong>the</strong> world and to make <strong>the</strong>m aspects only of <strong>the</strong> human<br />

m<strong>in</strong>d, which <strong>the</strong>n imposes <strong>the</strong>m arbitrarily upon nature accord<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to custom. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Goe<strong>the</strong>, beauty, <strong>for</strong> example,<br />

is not merely a matter of taste, but one of nature’s goals.<br />

Tantillo’s study of compensation is particularly helpful <strong>in</strong> this<br />

regard. This area of Goe<strong>the</strong>’s thought has received relatively<br />

less attention from ma<strong>in</strong>stream commentators, and her work<br />

is <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e even more valuable. She explores Goe<strong>the</strong>’s use of<br />

budgetary language to understand <strong>the</strong> “dynamic economic<br />

trade-offs” that go <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> <strong>for</strong>mation of an animal’s<br />

anatomy: “Goe<strong>the</strong> suggests that animals must balance each<br />

of <strong>the</strong>ir features aga<strong>in</strong>st o<strong>the</strong>rs. For example, animals with<br />

tusks have expended so much material on this feature that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y do not have enough material left over <strong>for</strong> horns on top<br />

of <strong>the</strong>ir heads.” She says that while <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory seems at first<br />

to emphasize limits, its great strength lies <strong>in</strong> its ability to show<br />

how animals create <strong>the</strong> most varied <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves out<br />

of <strong>the</strong> obstacles and with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> scope of <strong>the</strong> very limits <strong>the</strong>y<br />

face (116-117).<br />

For Goe<strong>the</strong>, organic change emerges out of <strong>the</strong> complex<br />

<strong>in</strong>teractions among an animal’s will to create, <strong>the</strong> circumscrib<strong>in</strong>g<br />

limits of its given “budget,” and environmental <strong>in</strong>fluences.<br />

Conventional notions of survival of <strong>the</strong> fittest would<br />

be <strong>for</strong> Goe<strong>the</strong> an “<strong>in</strong>adequate measure of an animal’s existence<br />

and natural selection a too mechanical explanation that<br />

does not really expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> root cause of change. Nature, not<br />

only concerned with a struggle <strong>for</strong> existence, seeks also to<br />

flourish” (128). With energy or material not consumed by<br />

that struggle, animals tend to create beautiful <strong>for</strong>ms that cannot<br />

be expla<strong>in</strong>ed entirely by <strong>the</strong> purpose those <strong>for</strong>ms might<br />

serve. For example, <strong>the</strong> curve and curl of horns might make<br />

<strong>the</strong>m less effective as weapons, but more beautiful (129).<br />

Tantillo’s discussion of <strong>the</strong> “type” is particularly illum<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Despite Goe<strong>the</strong>’s somewhat confus<strong>in</strong>g use of Platonic term<strong>in</strong>ology,<br />

she argues, “<strong>the</strong> purpose of <strong>the</strong> type is not to discover<br />

an underly<strong>in</strong>g similarity but to enable <strong>the</strong> study of fluid<br />

<strong>for</strong>ms.” “Although Goe<strong>the</strong>’s type seems to endorse a k<strong>in</strong>d of<br />

fixed standard with which to measure and understand nature,<br />

he is adamant that this standard must be flexible…Establish<strong>in</strong>g<br />

a type was <strong>in</strong>tended as a means to trace particular aspects<br />

of <strong>in</strong>dividual animals and species and not to fix or idealize<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>the</strong>mselves” (111).<br />

Goe<strong>the</strong>’s meteorology becomes emblematic of his general<br />

method; even <strong>in</strong> his treatment of <strong>in</strong>animate nature,<br />

Goe<strong>the</strong> emphasizes a will to create and a dynamic urge to<br />

reconcile opposites. Tantillo says “where <strong>the</strong> Cartesian world<br />

of dead matter operates accord<strong>in</strong>g to set rules, Goe<strong>the</strong>an<br />

matter comes to life,” and this can be seen particularly <strong>in</strong><br />

his discussions of clouds. In addition, Goe<strong>the</strong>’s discussion<br />

of clouds illustrates how crucial language is <strong>for</strong> him <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g<br />

visible <strong>the</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g dimension of phenomena. Goe<strong>the</strong><br />

praises <strong>the</strong> British scientist Luke Howard’s nomenclature <strong>for</strong><br />

first issue 2011 • 51

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!