20.05.2013 Views

Foucault, Biopolitics, and Governmentality

Foucault, Biopolitics, and Governmentality

Foucault, Biopolitics, and Governmentality

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

CATHERINE MILLS<br />

tive, since even at the simplest level “living means preference <strong>and</strong><br />

exclusion.” 28 Living necessarily involves polarities of valuation, such that an<br />

organism cannot be understood as indifferent to the environment in which<br />

it finds itself. Esposito goes on to emphasise that this means that disease <strong>and</strong><br />

health are both normative states in that both indicate new forms of life for<br />

the organism, <strong>and</strong> moreover, reveal the normal functioning of the body.<br />

Conditions of disease or biological abnormality are not simply deviations<br />

from a fixed prototype of the normal: they are instead normative forms of a<br />

qualitatively different order. Similarly, to be “normal” is not to coincide<br />

with a pre-established norm, but rather, to be able to harness <strong>and</strong> maintain<br />

one’s own normative power: to be normal is to be able to create new norms.<br />

In view of this radicalised immanence of life <strong>and</strong> norm, Esposito writes that<br />

“If Nazism stripped away every form of life, nailing it to its nude material<br />

existence, Canguilhem reconsigns every life to its form, making of it something<br />

unique <strong>and</strong> unrepeatable.” 29<br />

There is much in this account of the productive power of Canguilhem’s<br />

thinking around vital norms that I agree with. His analysis of the immanence<br />

of norms in life may well help to undermine the separation <strong>and</strong> mutual<br />

presupposition of the facticity of life <strong>and</strong> normative transcendentalism.<br />

Moreover, this analysis rejects an objectivist approach to life <strong>and</strong> emphasises<br />

instead the vital potential in life, in terms of the capacity to generate<br />

norms. However, it is exactly this productive power of the immanent<br />

normativity of life that points the way toward identifying several shortcomings<br />

with Esposito’s approach. For this normative capacity, the power<br />

to create norms that inheres in life, is itself conditioned by the environment<br />

or milieu in which an organism finds itself. Thus, one point, which Canguilhem<br />

is wholly committed to, that Esposito tends to skip over is that an<br />

organism by itself is never normal—er, what can be considered “normal” is<br />

wholly dependent on the relationship between the organism <strong>and</strong> its<br />

environment. Canguilhem writes:<br />

Taken separately, the living being <strong>and</strong> his environment are not normal:<br />

it is their relationship that makes them such. For any given form of life<br />

the environment is normal to the extent that it allows it fertility <strong>and</strong> a<br />

corresponding variety of forms such that, should changes in the<br />

environment occur, life will be able to find the solution to the problem<br />

of adaptation… in one of these forms. A living being is normal in any<br />

28 Canguilhem, The Normal <strong>and</strong> the Pathological, 136.<br />

29 Esposito, Bios, 189.<br />

82

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!