20.05.2013 Views

Foucault, Biopolitics, and Governmentality

Foucault, Biopolitics, and Governmentality

Foucault, Biopolitics, and Governmentality

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

CATHERINE MILLS<br />

of the living human being. In doing so, his analysis runs close to the<br />

arguments of liberal eugenicists <strong>and</strong> transhumanists, who valorise the possible<br />

plurality of bodily norms that technologies of enhancement are supposed<br />

to engender, without consideration of the ways in which those possibilities<br />

are delimited in advance by social norms that are lived in often less<br />

than conscious ways. 33 In this, then, Esposito risks a version of the liberal<br />

fantasy of escape from the founding conditions of human existence.<br />

The second point to make derives from this, for while the existence of<br />

human beings is fundamentally conditioned by social norms, it cannot be<br />

assumed that vital <strong>and</strong> social norms are conceptually equivalent. Rather,<br />

what needs to be taken into account is the disjuncture between vital <strong>and</strong><br />

social norms, <strong>and</strong> consequently, what requires explanation is the means by<br />

which they intermingle. In other words, vital <strong>and</strong> social norms may well be<br />

empirically inseparable, but they are nevertheless analytically distinguishable.<br />

In the postscript to The Normal <strong>and</strong> the Pathological, Canguilhem<br />

argues that while physiological norms are immanent to the organism,<br />

social norms have no equivalent immanence. In a living organism, norms<br />

are “presented without being represented, acting without deliberation or<br />

calculation,” such that there is “no divergence, no delay between rule <strong>and</strong><br />

regulation.” In contrast, rules in a social organization must be “represented,<br />

learned, remembered, applied.” 34 Further, while biological norms are geared<br />

toward a functional end, social norms are not— speaking of the “health” of<br />

a society is metaphoric in a way that speaking of the health of a living body<br />

is not. The point of this is that forms of social organisation cannot be<br />

understood as analogous to organisms; nor, then, can social norms be<br />

simply derived from organic norms.<br />

The point that social organisations are not analogous to organisms is<br />

significant for Canguilhem, because it allows him to avoid both the kind of<br />

socio-biology that derives social norms from biological norms, as well as a<br />

functional psycho-sociological version of adaptation that casts deviation<br />

from a social norm as abnormality. In light of this insistence on the<br />

exteriority of social norms, we would do well to qualify Esposito’s thesis on<br />

the “vitalisation of the norm.” While it is true that Canguilhem’s work<br />

points the way to a new philosophy of life that emphasises the productive<br />

power of the living in terms of the capacity to create norms, he also resists a<br />

33 For further discussion, see Catherine Mills, Futures of Reproduction: Bioethics <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Biopolitics</strong> (Dordrecht: Springer, 2011), especially Chapter 2, “Normal Life: Liberal<br />

Eugenics, Value Pluralism <strong>and</strong> Normalisation.”<br />

34 Ibid, 250.<br />

84

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!