12.11.2014 Views

Pragmatism and Theory in English Law - College of Social Sciences ...

Pragmatism and Theory in English Law - College of Social Sciences ...

Pragmatism and Theory in English Law - College of Social Sciences ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

94 The Weaknesses <strong>of</strong> the Pragmatic Tradition<br />

first thus laid down it was rational <strong>in</strong> serv<strong>in</strong>g the ends <strong>of</strong> the<br />

law as they were then perceived to be, but it cannot be<br />

rational today merely because it was rational <strong>in</strong> the past. But<br />

then how can we reconcile this dist<strong>in</strong>ction between historical<br />

explanation <strong>and</strong> forward-look<strong>in</strong>g purposiveness with our<br />

doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> precedent? Respect for precedent seems to blur<br />

this dist<strong>in</strong>ction, but there is really quite a simple explanation<br />

<strong>of</strong> this apparent paradox. There are, <strong>of</strong> course, different<br />

types <strong>of</strong> reason for mak<strong>in</strong>g decisions, just as there are many<br />

different types <strong>of</strong> goals which the legal system is designed to<br />

serve. Follow<strong>in</strong>g precedent serves a different k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> goal<br />

from those which may be served by specific rules <strong>of</strong> law; <strong>and</strong><br />

where the precedent <strong>in</strong> question seems unsatisfactory or<br />

seems to serve no sensible goal <strong>in</strong> itself, it may seem perverse<br />

to suggest that follow<strong>in</strong>g the precedent can still somehow be<br />

seen as rationally serv<strong>in</strong>g goals <strong>of</strong> the law. Bentham <strong>in</strong>deed<br />

was conv<strong>in</strong>ced that to follow precedent was to act "without<br />

reason, to the declared exclusion <strong>of</strong> reason <strong>and</strong> thereby <strong>in</strong><br />

opposition to reason." 8 But Bentham was wrong. Clearly<br />

there are many good reasons for follow<strong>in</strong>g a precedent<br />

irrespective <strong>of</strong> whether the decision was itself a good<br />

rational decision when made, such as the desire to act consistently,<br />

the desire to make the law more certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> predictable,<br />

the desire to economise on judicial decision<br />

mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> so on. All these are perfectly rational grounds<br />

for hav<strong>in</strong>g a system <strong>of</strong> precedent, though I am not <strong>of</strong> course<br />

say<strong>in</strong>g anyth<strong>in</strong>g about the weight <strong>of</strong> these reasons, nor<br />

about the extent to which it is best to serve these goals rather<br />

than other, more substantive goals, <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> the merits <strong>of</strong><br />

the issue itself. In any event, I th<strong>in</strong>k it clear that Holmes<br />

underestimated the value <strong>of</strong> sheer tradition <strong>in</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

8 Constitutional Code (collected works <strong>of</strong> Jeremy Bentham) (ed. F. Rosenn<br />

<strong>and</strong> J. H. Burns, 1983), vol. 1, p. 434.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!