26.03.2013 Views

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Then why do young children, even when <strong>the</strong>y are intellectually<br />

serious, make animistic or personifying remarks<br />

fairly <strong>of</strong>ten, although not so <strong>of</strong>ten as Piaget claimed? What<br />

functions does <strong>the</strong> mode <strong>of</strong> reasoning behind animistic or<br />

personifying errors have? Both Carey (1985) and Inagaki<br />

and Hatano (1987) propose that, though young children are<br />

able to classify entities into ontological categories, when<br />

<strong>the</strong>y have to infer an object’s unknown attributes or reactions,<br />

<strong>the</strong> children apply <strong>the</strong>ir knowledge about human<br />

beings to o<strong>the</strong>r animate objects or even to inanimate objects.<br />

This is probably because <strong>the</strong>y do not have rich categorical<br />

knowledge, and thus have to rely on ANALOGY in inferences.<br />

Because <strong>the</strong>y are intimately familiar with humans,<br />

although necessarily novices in most o<strong>the</strong>r domains, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

can most pr<strong>of</strong>itably use <strong>the</strong>ir knowledge about humans as a<br />

source analogue for making analogies.<br />

Inagaki and Hatano (1987) propose that animistic or personifying<br />

tendencies <strong>of</strong> young children are products <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

active minds and basically adaptive natures. Young children’s<br />

personification or person analogies may lead <strong>the</strong>m to<br />

accurate predictions for animate objects phylogenetically<br />

similar to humans. It can also provide justification for a variety<br />

<strong>of</strong> experiences, sometimes even with phylogenetically<br />

less similar objects, such as trees or flowers. Young children<br />

may have learned <strong>the</strong>se heuristic values through <strong>the</strong>ir prior<br />

contacts with a variety <strong>of</strong> animate objects. The analogies<br />

young children make may involve structurally inaccurate<br />

mapping (e.g., mapping <strong>the</strong> relation between humans and<br />

food to that between plants and water), and induce biased<br />

reasoning (neglect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> roles <strong>of</strong> nutrients in <strong>the</strong> soil and<br />

photosyn<strong>the</strong>sis). Although young children may carry analogy<br />

beyond its proper limits, and produce false inferences,<br />

<strong>the</strong>y can generate “educated guesses” by analogies, relying<br />

on <strong>the</strong>ir only familiar source analogue <strong>of</strong> a person (Holyoak<br />

and Thagard 1995). Animistic errors and overattribution <strong>of</strong><br />

human characteristics to nonhuman animate objects should<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore be regarded as accidental by-products <strong>of</strong> this reasoning<br />

process. Because <strong>the</strong>ir personification is subject to a<br />

variety <strong>of</strong> constraints, such as checking <strong>the</strong> plausibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

inference against what is known about <strong>the</strong> target, it does not<br />

produce many personifying errors, except for assigning mental<br />

states to nonhumans.<br />

How can we explain animistic thinking among indigenous<br />

adults? According to Atran (forthcoming), in cultures<br />

throughout <strong>the</strong> world it is common to classify all entities into<br />

four ontological categories (humans, nonhuman animals,<br />

plants, and nonliving things, including artifacts), and to<br />

arrange animals and plants hierarchically and more or less<br />

accurately because such taxonomies are products <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

human mind’s natural classification scheme (see also FOLK<br />

BIOLOGY). Because indigenous people generally possess rich<br />

knowledge about major animals and plants in <strong>the</strong>ir ecological<br />

niche, <strong>the</strong>ir animistic and personifying remarks cannot result<br />

from having to rely on <strong>the</strong> person analogy, except for poorly<br />

understood nonnatural entities like God (Barrett and Keil<br />

1996). Such remarks seem to be products <strong>of</strong> cultural beliefs,<br />

acquired through discourse about a specific class <strong>of</strong> entities.<br />

Mead’s early observation (1932) that children in <strong>the</strong> Manus<br />

tribes were less animistic than adults lends support to this<br />

conjecture. Animistic or personifying explanations are wide-<br />

Animism 29<br />

spread, but <strong>the</strong>y are more about <strong>the</strong> metaphysical or imaginative<br />

universe than about <strong>the</strong> real world (Atran 1990). Even<br />

contemporary Japanese culture, outside <strong>the</strong> science classroom<br />

does not consider it a silly idea that large, old inanimate entities<br />

(e.g., giant rocks, mountains) have CONSCIOUSNESS.<br />

See also CONCEPTUAL CHANGE; CULTURAL EVOLUTION;<br />

CULTURAL SYMBOLISM; CULTURAL VARIATION; MAGIC AND<br />

SUPERSTITION; NATIVISM<br />

—Giyoo Hatano<br />

References<br />

Atran, S. (1990). <strong>Cognitive</strong> Foundations <strong>of</strong> Natural History. Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge University Press.<br />

Atran, S. (Forthcoming). Folk biology and <strong>the</strong> anthropology <strong>of</strong> science:<br />

<strong>Cognitive</strong> universals and cultural particulars. Brain and<br />

Behavioral <strong>Sciences</strong>.<br />

Barrett, J. L., and F. C. Keil. (1996). Conceptualizing a nonnatural<br />

entity: Anthropomorphism in God concepts. <strong>Cognitive</strong> Psychology<br />

31: 219–247.<br />

Carey, S. (1985). Conceptual Change in Childhood. Cambridge,<br />

MA: <strong>MIT</strong> Press.<br />

Gelman, R., E. Spelke, and E. Meck. (1983). What preschoolers<br />

know about animate and inanimate objects. In D. Rogers and J.<br />

A. Sloboda, Eds., The Acquisition <strong>of</strong> Symbolic Skills. New<br />

York: Plenum Press, pp. 297–326.<br />

Gelman, S. A., J. Coley, and G. M. Gottfried. (1994). Essentialist<br />

beliefs in children: The acquisition <strong>of</strong> concepts and <strong>the</strong>ories. In<br />

L. A. Hirschfeld and S. A. Gelman, Eds., Mapping <strong>the</strong> Mind:<br />

Domain Specificity in Cognition and Culture. Hillsdale, NJ:<br />

Erlbaum, pp. 341–365.<br />

Holyoak, K. J., and P. Thagard. (1995). Mental Leaps. Cambridge,<br />

MA: <strong>MIT</strong> Press.<br />

Inagaki, K., and G. Hatano. (1987). Young children’s spontaneous<br />

personification as analogy. Child Development 58: 1013–1020.<br />

Laurendeau, M., and A. Pinard. (1962). Causal Thinking in <strong>the</strong><br />

Child: A Genetic and Experimental Approach. New York:<br />

International Universities Press.<br />

Lévy-Bruhl, L. (1910). How Natives Think. Translated by Princeton:<br />

Princeton University Press, 1985. Originally published as Les<br />

fonctions mentales dans les sociétés inférieures. Paris: Alcan.<br />

Mead, M. (1932). An investigation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> thought <strong>of</strong> primitive children<br />

with special reference to animism. Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Royal<br />

Anthropological Institute 62: 173–190.<br />

Piaget, J. (1926). The Child’s Conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> World. Translated<br />

by Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanheld, 1960. Originally published<br />

as La représentation du monde chez l’enfant. Paris:<br />

Presses Universitaires de France.<br />

Richards, D. D., and R. S. Siegler. (1984). The effects <strong>of</strong> task<br />

requirements on children’s life judgments. Child Development<br />

55: 1687–1696.<br />

Simons, D. J., and F. C. Keil. (1995). An abstract to concrete shift<br />

in <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> biological thought: The inside story.<br />

Cognition 56: 129–163.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>r Readings<br />

Bullock, M. (1985). Animism in childhood thinking: A new look at<br />

an old question. Developmental Psychology 21: 217–225.<br />

Dennis, W. (1953). Animistic thinking among college and university<br />

students. Scientific Monthly 76: 247–249.<br />

Dolgin, K. G., and D. A. Behrend. (1984). Children’s knowledge<br />

about animates and inanimates. Child Development 55: 1646–<br />

1650.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!