26.03.2013 Views

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

John Lucy, an anthropologist, has written about language<br />

differences associated with perceptual differences. For<br />

example, speakers <strong>of</strong> languages with different basic color<br />

vocabularies might sort nonprimary colors (e.g., turquoise,<br />

chartreuse) in slightly different ways. But such subtle<br />

effects were hardly what Sapir and Whorf had in mind when<br />

<strong>the</strong>y wrote about how language might be related to, or might<br />

even shape, its speakers’ worldview (e.g., time, causality,<br />

ontological categories).<br />

One notable exception is <strong>the</strong> psychologist Alfred<br />

Bloom’s intriguing claim that <strong>the</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> a distinct counterfactual<br />

marker in <strong>the</strong> Chinese language might make it difficult<br />

for Chinese speakers to think counterfactually—that is,<br />

to think hypo<strong>the</strong>tically about what is not true (e.g., If Plato<br />

had been able to read Chinese, he could have . . .). Upon<br />

close scrutiny, however, Chinese speakers’ purported difficulty<br />

in understanding Bloom’s counterfactual stories disappeared<br />

when researchers such as Terry Au and Lisa Liu<br />

rewrote those stories in idiomatic Chinese with proper counterfactual<br />

markers. With 20/20 hindsight, perhaps we should<br />

have realized that Bloom’s initial finding had to be too fascinating<br />

to be true. Note that when we feel lucky and realize<br />

that things could have turned out badly but didn’t, or when<br />

we regret having done something and wish that we had<br />

acted differently, we have to think counterfactually. How<br />

can something so fundamental and pervasive in human<br />

thinking be difficult in any human language?<br />

Despite early disappointing efforts to uncover evidence<br />

for language shaping thought, a “Whorfian Renaissance”<br />

seems to be in <strong>the</strong> making. For instance, <strong>the</strong> anthropologist<br />

Stephen Levinson has reported interesting variations in spatial<br />

language across cultures (see LANGUAGE AND CUL-<br />

TURE). However, how each language carves up space seems<br />

to be principled—influenced by <strong>the</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> gravity<br />

(e.g., up, down), human perception (e.g., near, far, front,<br />

back) and so forth—ra<strong>the</strong>r than random or arbitrary. Moreover,<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is as yet no evidence for fundamental differences<br />

in spatial cognition associated with linguistic variations. For<br />

example, unlike some Papuan languages, English has no<br />

simple word meaning “that far away up <strong>the</strong>re.” Are English<br />

speakers less capable than Papuan speakers to construe such<br />

a location? Probably not. While <strong>the</strong> jury is still out for <strong>the</strong><br />

Sapir-Whorf hypo<strong>the</strong>sis, it is probably safe to say that<br />

important aspects <strong>of</strong> our worldview are unlikely to be at <strong>the</strong><br />

mercy <strong>of</strong> arbitrary aspects <strong>of</strong> our language.<br />

How about <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way around? By virtue <strong>of</strong> being<br />

human, we tend to perceive, organize, and reason about <strong>the</strong><br />

world in certain ways. Do languages build upon our perceptual<br />

categories and conceptual organization? Consider color perception.<br />

Four-month-old babies prefer looking at primary colors<br />

(red, blue, green, yellow) to colors near <strong>the</strong> boundaries <strong>of</strong><br />

primary colors; toddlers can identify primary colors better than<br />

nonprimary ones. Interestingly, anthropologists Brent Berlin<br />

and Paul Kay found that, if a language has fewer than five<br />

basic color words, it would include red, blue, green, and yellow<br />

(in addition to black and white). Nonprimary colors such<br />

as brown, pink, orange, and purple are encoded only in languages<br />

that have encoded <strong>the</strong> four primary colors (see COLOR<br />

CATEGORIZATION). Perceptual salience, <strong>the</strong>n, seems to shape<br />

<strong>the</strong> encoding <strong>of</strong> color words ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way around.<br />

Language and Thought 445<br />

Our cognition also seems to shape our language. For<br />

instance, when asked in <strong>the</strong>ir native language “Paul amazes<br />

Mary. Why?” and “Paul admires Mary. Why?”, <strong>the</strong> psychologist<br />

Roger Brown found that both Chinese and English<br />

speakers tended to talk about something amazing about Paul<br />

and something admirable about Mary. Note that in English,<br />

“amazing” and “admirable”—ra<strong>the</strong>r than “amazable” and<br />

“admiring”—are entrenched adjectives for describing people’s<br />

disposition. These cognitive causal schemas, <strong>the</strong>n,<br />

might be a universal and may have influenced <strong>the</strong> derivation<br />

<strong>of</strong> dispositional adjectives in English, ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

way around.<br />

One more central issue in <strong>the</strong> study <strong>of</strong> language and<br />

thought: Are our abilities to learn and use language part <strong>of</strong><br />

our general intelligence? Or, are <strong>the</strong>y subserved by a special<br />

“language faculty”? Recent findings on language-specific<br />

impairments (i.e., language delay or disorder experienced<br />

by children who are not hearing or cognitively impaired)<br />

and Williams syndrome (i.e., extreme mental retardation<br />

with almost intact language abilities) suggest that cognition<br />

and language can be decoupled (see LANGUAGE IMPAIR-<br />

MENT, DEVELOPMENTAL). In short, although language and<br />

thought might be quite modular (see also MODULARITY OF<br />

MIND), <strong>the</strong>re is some evidence for our cognition and perception<br />

shaping <strong>the</strong> evolution <strong>of</strong> our language. Evidence for<br />

influence in <strong>the</strong> opposite direction, however, seems more<br />

elusive.<br />

See also CATEGORIZATION; IMAGERY; MODULARITY AND<br />

LANGUAGE; NATIVISM; VYGOTSKY<br />

—Terry Au<br />

References<br />

Au, T. K. (1983). Chinese and English counterfactuals: The Sapir-<br />

Whorf hypo<strong>the</strong>sis revisited. Cognition 15: 155–187.<br />

Au, T. K. (1986). A verb is worth a thousand words: The causes<br />

and consequences <strong>of</strong> interpersonal events implicit in language.<br />

Journal <strong>of</strong> Memory and Language 25: 104–122.<br />

Baillargeon, R. (1993). The object concept revisited: New directions<br />

in <strong>the</strong> investigation <strong>of</strong> infants’ physical knowledge. In C.<br />

Granrud, Ed., Visual Perception and Cognition in Infancy.<br />

Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, pp. 265–315.<br />

Bellugi, U., A. Bihrle, H. Neville, and S. Doherty. (1992). Language,<br />

cognition, and brain organization in a neurodevelopmental<br />

disorder. In M. Gunnar and C. Nelson, Eds.,<br />

Developmental Behavioral Neuroscience. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum,<br />

pp. 201–232.<br />

Berlin, B., and P. Kay. (1969). Basic Color Terms: Their Universality<br />

and Evolution. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University <strong>of</strong><br />

California Press.<br />

Bloom, A. H. (1981). The Linguistic Shaping <strong>of</strong> Thought: A Study<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Impact <strong>of</strong> Language on Thinking in China and <strong>the</strong> West.<br />

Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.<br />

Bornstein, M. H. (1975). Qualities <strong>of</strong> color vision in infancy. Journal<br />

<strong>of</strong> Experimental Child Psychology 19: 410–419.<br />

Brown, R., and D. Fisher. (1983). The psychological causality<br />

implicit in language. Cognition 14: 237–273.<br />

Chomsky, N. (1959). A review <strong>of</strong> B. F. Skinner’s monograph “Verbal<br />

Behavior.” Language 35: 26–58.<br />

Goldin-Meadow, S., and C. Mylander. (1990). Beyond <strong>the</strong> input<br />

given: The child’s role in <strong>the</strong> acquisition <strong>of</strong> language. Language<br />

66: 323–355.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!