26.03.2013 Views

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

180 Conceptual Change<br />

concept, perhaps because <strong>the</strong>y occur more frequently in a<br />

set <strong>of</strong> experiences. A young child might weight shape<br />

somewhat more heavily in her concept <strong>of</strong> a bath towel than<br />

texture, while an older child might do <strong>the</strong> opposite. In its<br />

simplest form, such a developmental change may not connect<br />

to any o<strong>the</strong>r relations or beliefs, such as why texture is<br />

now more important. An older child might disagree with a<br />

younger one on identifying some marginal feature <strong>of</strong> bath<br />

towels, and while we might <strong>the</strong>reby attribute this difference<br />

to conceptual change, we might not see <strong>the</strong> concepts<br />

as really being very different.<br />

Changes in feature weightings and dimensional value<br />

shifts are ubiquitous in cognitive science studies <strong>of</strong> concepts.<br />

They are seen at all ages ranging from studies <strong>of</strong><br />

infant categorization to adult novice-to-expert shifts (see<br />

INFANT COGNITION and EXPERTISE). Any time that some bit<br />

<strong>of</strong> information is incrementally added to a knowledge base<br />

and results in a different feature weighting, such a change<br />

occurs. When such changes have no o<strong>the</strong>r obvious consequences<br />

for how knowledge in a domain is represented, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

constitute <strong>the</strong> most minimal sense <strong>of</strong> conceptual change,<br />

and for many who contrast “learning” with true conceptual<br />

change, not a real case at all (Carey 1991).<br />

2. Shifting use <strong>of</strong> different sorts <strong>of</strong> properties and relations.<br />

Conceptual change could occur because <strong>of</strong> changes in<br />

<strong>the</strong> kinds <strong>of</strong> feature used in representations. Infants and<br />

young children have been said to use perceptual and not conceptual<br />

features to represent classes <strong>of</strong> things, or perceptual<br />

and not functional ones, or concrete and not abstract ones<br />

(e.g., Werner and Kaplan 1963). More recently, young children<br />

are said to use one-place predicates and not higherorder<br />

relational ones (Gentner and Toupin 1988), or to rely<br />

heavily on shape-based features early on in some contexts<br />

(Smith, Jones, and Landau 1996). Similar arguments have<br />

been made about novice to expert shifts in adults (Chi, Feltovich,<br />

and Glaser 1981) and even about <strong>the</strong> evolution <strong>of</strong><br />

concepts from those in “primitive” cultures to those in more<br />

“advanced” ones (cf. Horton 1967; see also LURIA).<br />

Several forms <strong>of</strong> conceptual change can be captured by<br />

shifts in what feature types are used in concepts. Despite a<br />

wide range <strong>of</strong> proposals in this area, however, it is striking<br />

how many have always been controversial, especially in<br />

claims <strong>of</strong> cross-cultural differences (Cole and Means 1981).<br />

There is no consensus on changes in <strong>the</strong> sorts <strong>of</strong> properties,<br />

relations, or both available at different points in development,<br />

expertise, or historical change, nor on <strong>the</strong> very real<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> no true changes in <strong>the</strong> availability <strong>of</strong> property<br />

types.<br />

Part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem is <strong>the</strong> need for better <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong><br />

property types. It is difficult to make claims about perceptual<br />

to conceptual shifts, or perceptual to functional shifts, if<br />

<strong>the</strong> contrast between perceptual and conceptual features is<br />

murky. Claims <strong>of</strong> changes in feature types <strong>the</strong>refore need to<br />

attend closely to philosophical analyses <strong>of</strong> properties and<br />

relations, which in turn need to attend more to <strong>the</strong> empirical<br />

facts.<br />

3. Changes in computations performed on features.<br />

Conceptual change can also arise from new kinds <strong>of</strong> computations<br />

performed on a constant set <strong>of</strong> features, such as from<br />

tabulations <strong>of</strong> features based on frequency and correlational<br />

information, to more rulelike organizations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same features<br />

(Sloman 1996). In o<strong>the</strong>r cases, <strong>the</strong>re have been claims<br />

<strong>of</strong> changes from prelogical to quasi-logical computations<br />

over features (Inhelder and Piaget 1958), or changes from<br />

integral to separable operations on features and dimensions<br />

(Kemler and Smith 1978); or changes from feature frequency<br />

tabulations to feature correlation tabulations.<br />

Although most models tend to propose changes in computations<br />

that apply across all areas <strong>of</strong> cognition, such transitions<br />

can also occur in circumscribed domains <strong>of</strong> thought<br />

even as <strong>the</strong>re are no global changes in computational ability<br />

(Chi 1992). Second, <strong>the</strong>se models do not require that concepts<br />

be interrelated in a larger structure. They are neutral in<br />

that respect and thus allow each concept to change on its<br />

own. In practice, this is highly implausible and may in <strong>the</strong><br />

end render such models inadequate because <strong>the</strong>y fail to<br />

make stronger claims about links among concepts.<br />

There are also cases where <strong>the</strong>re is no absolute change in<br />

feature or computational types, but ra<strong>the</strong>r a strong change in<br />

<strong>the</strong> ratio <strong>of</strong> types. Thus a younger child may have true conceptual<br />

or functional features but may have ten times as<br />

many perceptual ones in her concepts, whereas an older<br />

child may have <strong>the</strong> opposite ratio. Similarly, a younger child<br />

may perform logical computations on feature sets, but may<br />

do so much more rarely and may more frequently resort to<br />

simpler probabilistic tabulations. This variant is important<br />

because it <strong>of</strong>fers a very different characterization <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

younger child in terms <strong>of</strong> basic competencies. Younger children<br />

are not incapable <strong>of</strong> representing certain feature types<br />

or engaging in certain computations; ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>y do so<br />

much less <strong>of</strong>ten, perhaps as a function <strong>of</strong> being much more<br />

inexperienced in so many domains (Keil 1989).<br />

4. Theoretic changes, where <strong>the</strong>ories spawn o<strong>the</strong>rs and<br />

<strong>the</strong>reby create new sets <strong>of</strong> concepts. The most dramatic<br />

kinds <strong>of</strong> conceptual change, and those occupying most discussions<br />

in cognitive science at large, are those that view<br />

concepts as embedded in larger explanatory structures, usually<br />

known as “<strong>the</strong>ories,” and whose changes honor DOMAIN<br />

SPECIFICITY. Sweeping structural changes are said to occur<br />

among whole sets <strong>of</strong> related concepts in a domain. For<br />

example, a change in one concept in biology will naturally<br />

lead to simultaneous changes in o<strong>the</strong>r biological concepts<br />

because <strong>the</strong>y as a cluster tend to complement each o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

symbiotically. Within this type, three kinds <strong>of</strong> change are<br />

normally described: (a) birth <strong>of</strong> new <strong>the</strong>ories and concepts<br />

through <strong>the</strong> death <strong>of</strong> older ones (Gopnik and Wellman<br />

1994); (b) gradual evolution <strong>of</strong> new <strong>the</strong>ories and concepts<br />

out <strong>of</strong> old ones in a manner that eventually leaves no traces<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> earlier ones (Wiser and Carey 1983); and (c) birth <strong>of</strong><br />

new <strong>the</strong>ories and attendant concepts in a manner that leaves<br />

<strong>the</strong> old ones intact (Carey 1985).<br />

One key issue in choosing among <strong>the</strong>se kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretic<br />

change is <strong>the</strong> extent to which concepts <strong>of</strong> one type are<br />

incommensurable or contradictory with those <strong>of</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

type (Kuhn 1970, 1982). Kuhn suggested that conceptual<br />

changes in domains could lead to “paradigm shifts” in<br />

which concepts in a prior system <strong>of</strong> beliefs might not even<br />

be understandable in terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> new set <strong>of</strong> beliefs, just as<br />

concepts in that newer system might not be understandable<br />

in terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> older one. The ideas <strong>of</strong> paradigm shifts and

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!