26.03.2013 Views

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

328 Freud, Sigmund<br />

Dummett, M. (1973). Frege: Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Language. London:<br />

Duckworth.<br />

Fodor, J. (1975). The Language <strong>of</strong> Thought. New York: Thomas<br />

Crowell.<br />

Frege, G. (1879). Begriffsschrift: a formula language, modeled<br />

upon that <strong>of</strong> arithmetic, for pure thought. In Jean Van Heihenoort,<br />

Ed., 1967, From Frege to Goedel: A Source Book in<br />

Ma<strong>the</strong>matical Logic, 1879–1931. Cambridge: Harvard University<br />

Press, pp. 5–82.<br />

Frege, G. (1884/1980). The Foundations <strong>of</strong> Arithmetic. Evanston,<br />

IL: Northwestern University Press.<br />

Frege, G. (1891). On Sense and Reference. In Peter, Geach, and<br />

Max Black, Eds., (1993). Translations from <strong>the</strong> Philosophical<br />

Writings <strong>of</strong> G Frege. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 56–78 (<strong>the</strong>re translated<br />

as “On Sense and Meaning”).<br />

Frege, G. (1893, 1903/1966). Grundgesetze der Arithmetik.<br />

Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlag.<br />

Frege, G. (1918). Thoughts. In Brian McGuiness, Ed., 1984, Collected<br />

Papers. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 351–372.<br />

Frege, G. (1984). Collected Papers. Brian McGuiness, Ed. Oxford:<br />

Blackwell.<br />

Husserl, E. (1903/1980). Logische Untersuchungen. Tuebingen:<br />

Max Niemeyer.<br />

Schoenfinkel, M. (1924). On <strong>the</strong> building blocks <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical<br />

logic. In J. Van Heihenoort, Ed., 1967, From Frege to Goedel: A<br />

Source Book in Ma<strong>the</strong>matical Logic, 1879–1931. Cambridge,<br />

MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 357–366.<br />

Wright, C. (1983). Frege’s Conception <strong>of</strong> Numbers as Objects.<br />

Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press.<br />

Freud, Sigmund<br />

A prolific and gifted writer, whose broad learning extended<br />

from neurophysiology and EVOLUTION to <strong>the</strong> literature <strong>of</strong><br />

six languages, Sigmund Freud (1826–1939) was one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

most influential scientists <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> late nineteenth and early<br />

twentieth centuries. He was also one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most controversial<br />

scientists <strong>of</strong> any time, so much so that both his critics<br />

and admirers have occasionally succumbed to <strong>the</strong> temptation<br />

to deny that he was a scientist at all.<br />

Freud’s positive and negative reputations flow from <strong>the</strong><br />

same source—<strong>the</strong> extraordinary scope <strong>of</strong> his <strong>the</strong>ories.<br />

Although <strong>the</strong> notions <strong>of</strong> unconscious ideas and processes<br />

did not originate with Freud, having philosophical antecedents<br />

in Gottfried Leibniz’s (1646–1716) <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong><br />

petites perceptions and psychiatric antecedents in <strong>the</strong> work<br />

<strong>of</strong>, inter alia, Pierre Janet (1859–1947), Freud made <strong>the</strong>m<br />

<strong>the</strong> centerpiece <strong>of</strong> his complex <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind. Unlike<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r psychiatrists, Freud took unconscious ideas and processes<br />

to be critical in explaining <strong>the</strong> behavior <strong>of</strong> all people<br />

in all circumstances and not merely <strong>the</strong> outré actions <strong>of</strong><br />

psychotics. Unlike Leibniz and his followers, Freud presented<br />

unconscious ideas not merely as a <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

necessity, but as <strong>the</strong> key to human action. Through his<br />

spirited defense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> necessity and importance <strong>of</strong> unconscious<br />

ideas and processes, he gave <strong>the</strong>se concepts <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

respectability, almost in spite <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir associations<br />

with him.<br />

The explanatory scope <strong>of</strong> unconscious ideas and processes<br />

was enormous for Freud, because he saw psychoanalysis<br />

(see PSYCHOANALYSIS, CONTEMPORARY VIEWS OF<br />

and PSYCHOANALYSIS, HISTORY OF) as bridging <strong>the</strong> gap<br />

between <strong>the</strong> biological and <strong>the</strong> “human” sciences. Freud’s<br />

early training in neurophysiology led him to try to ground<br />

psychological <strong>the</strong>orizing in <strong>the</strong> known structures <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

brain. His incomplete manuscript, “Project for a Scientific<br />

Psychology” attempted to relate specific psychological<br />

functions, such as learning and memory, to recently discovered<br />

properties <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> neurons. In this respect, his<br />

methodological principles exactly paralleled <strong>the</strong> current<br />

view in cognitive science that psychological <strong>the</strong>orizing<br />

must be consistent with and informed by <strong>the</strong> most recent<br />

knowledge in neuroscience. Freud was also an avid supporter<br />

<strong>of</strong> DARWIN and was explicit in stating that his <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

<strong>of</strong> sexual and self-preservative instincts was firmly rooted<br />

in (evolutionary) biology. Prototypical <strong>of</strong> his syn<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

approach to knowledge, he made a bold conjecture about<br />

an important relation between <strong>the</strong> findings <strong>of</strong> neurophysiology<br />

and evolutionary biology. If, as nearly all psychologists<br />

agreed, <strong>the</strong> mind functioned as a reflex, <strong>the</strong>n it<br />

required constant stimulation, and if, as Darwin argued,<br />

<strong>the</strong> sexual instinct is one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two most important forces<br />

governing animal life, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>se findings could be<br />

brought toge<strong>the</strong>r under a more comprehensive <strong>the</strong>ory that<br />

sexual instincts (libido) drove <strong>the</strong> nervous system.<br />

Although Freud, his disciples, and his critics <strong>of</strong>ten present<br />

libido <strong>the</strong>ory as an extrapolation from <strong>the</strong> sexual difficulties<br />

<strong>of</strong> his patients, its real strength and appeal came from<br />

its plausible biological premises.<br />

Thanks to Darwin’s influence, sexuality also played an<br />

important role in <strong>the</strong> social sciences <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> late nineteenth<br />

century. A methodological imperative <strong>of</strong> evolutionary<br />

anthropology and sociology was to connect sophisticated<br />

human achievements to “primitive” conditions shared with<br />

animals, and sexual behavior was <strong>the</strong> most obvious point<br />

<strong>of</strong> connection. Given <strong>the</strong>se trends in social science, Freud<br />

was able to make “upward” connections between psychoanalysis<br />

and <strong>the</strong> social sciences, as well as “downward”<br />

connections to neurophysiology and biology. In his efforts<br />

to find links among all <strong>the</strong> “mental” sciences, Freud’s<br />

methodological approach again bears a striking resemblance<br />

to <strong>the</strong> interdisciplinary emphasis <strong>of</strong> current cognitive<br />

science. This approach was also <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

tremendous appeal <strong>of</strong> psychoanalysis: he believed that he<br />

had a <strong>the</strong>ory that could provide biologically grounded<br />

explanations, in terms <strong>of</strong> sexual and self-preservative<br />

instincts and <strong>the</strong> various mental processes that operated on<br />

<strong>the</strong>m, for everything from psychotic symptoms, dreams,<br />

and jokes to cultural practices such as art and religion.<br />

Freud’s <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> CONSCIOUSNESS and <strong>the</strong> EMOTIONS<br />

were also <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> an interdisciplinary syn<strong>the</strong>sis<br />

between psychiatry and philosophy. Individuals whose<br />

behavior was driven by natural, but unconscious, emotional<br />

forces needed treatment in order to gain control <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>ir lives by bringing <strong>the</strong> forces that govern <strong>the</strong>m to consciousness.<br />

This was possible, Freud believed, because<br />

affective states were also cognitive and so could be made<br />

conscious through <strong>the</strong>ir ideational components. Although<br />

<strong>the</strong> Project <strong>of</strong>fered some speculations about <strong>the</strong> qualitative<br />

character <strong>of</strong> consciousness, Freud’s later approach<br />

was functionalist. Conscious ideas differed from <strong>the</strong><br />

unconscious, because <strong>the</strong>y could be expressed verbally,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!