26.03.2013 Views

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences - Cryptome

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

“Every linguist has read Syntactic Structures” at LF, and<br />

because QR may iterate, <strong>the</strong> representations in (2) for<br />

“Every linguist has read some book by Chomsky”.<br />

(1) [ every linguist1 [ t1 has read Syntactic Structures]]<br />

(2) a. [ every linguist1 [ some book by Chomsky2 [ t1 has<br />

read t1 ]]]<br />

b. [ some book by Chomsky2 [ every linguist1 [ t1 has<br />

read t2 ]]]<br />

With <strong>the</strong> aid <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> syntactic notions <strong>of</strong> “trace <strong>of</strong> movement”<br />

(t1 , t2 ) and “c-command” (both <strong>of</strong> which are independently<br />

necessary within syntactic <strong>the</strong>ory), <strong>the</strong> logically<br />

significant distinctions <strong>of</strong> open and closed sentence, and <strong>of</strong><br />

relative scope <strong>of</strong> quantifiers, can be easily defined with<br />

respect to <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> representations in (1) and (2). Interpreting<br />

<strong>the</strong> trace in (1) as a variable, “t1 has read Syntactic<br />

Structures” stands as an open sentence, falling within <strong>the</strong><br />

scope <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> c-commanding quantifier phrase “every<br />

linguist1 ;” similar remarks hold for (2), except that (2a)<br />

and (2b) can be recognized as representing distinct scope<br />

orderings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> quantifiers (see Heim 1982; May 1985,<br />

1989; Hornstein and Weinberg 1990; Fox 1995; Beghelli<br />

and Stowell 1997; and Reinhart 1997 for fur<strong>the</strong>r discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> treatment <strong>of</strong> quantification within <strong>the</strong> LF<br />

approach). A wide range <strong>of</strong> arguments have been made for<br />

<strong>the</strong> LF approach to logical form. Illustrative <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong><br />

argument presented is <strong>the</strong> argument from antecedent-contained<br />

deletion (May 1985). A sentence such as “Dulles<br />

suspected everyone that Angleton did” has a verb phrase<br />

elided (its position is marked by <strong>the</strong> pro-form “did”). If,<br />

however, <strong>the</strong> ellipsis is to be “reconstructed” on <strong>the</strong> basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> surface form, <strong>the</strong> result will be a structural regress,<br />

as <strong>the</strong> “antecedent” verb phrase, “suspected everyone that<br />

Angleton did” itself contains <strong>the</strong> ellipsis site. However, if<br />

<strong>the</strong> reconstruction is defined with respect to a structure<br />

derived by QR:<br />

(3) everyone that Angleton did [Dulles suspected t],<br />

<strong>the</strong> antecedent is now <strong>the</strong> VP “suspected t,” obtaining, properly,<br />

an LF-representation comparable in form to that which<br />

would result if <strong>the</strong>re had been no deletion:<br />

(4) everyone that Angleton suspected t [Dulles suspected t].<br />

Among o<strong>the</strong>r well-known arguments for LF are weak<br />

crossover (Chomsky 1976), <strong>the</strong> interaction <strong>of</strong> quantifier<br />

scope and bound variable anaphora (Higginbotham 1980;<br />

Higginbotham and May 1981), superiority effects with multiple<br />

wh-constructions (Aoun, Hornstein, and Sportiche<br />

1981) and wh-complementation in languages without overt<br />

wh-movement (Huang 1982). Over <strong>the</strong> past two decades,<br />

<strong>the</strong>re has been active discussion in linguistic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

precise nature <strong>of</strong> representations at LF, in particular with<br />

respect to <strong>the</strong> representation <strong>of</strong> binding (see BINDING THE-<br />

ORY) as this pertains to quantification and ANAPHORA, and<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> semantic interpretation <strong>of</strong> such representations (cf.<br />

Larson and Segal 1995). This has taken place within a<br />

milieu <strong>of</strong> evolving conceptions <strong>of</strong> SYNTAX and SEMANTICS<br />

and has led to considerable refinement in our conceptions <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> structure <strong>of</strong> logical forms and <strong>the</strong> range <strong>of</strong> phenomena<br />

Logical Form in Linguistics 487<br />

that can be analyzed. Constant in <strong>the</strong>se discussions has been<br />

<strong>the</strong> assumption that logical form is integrated into syntactic<br />

description generally, and hence that <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>sis that natural<br />

languages are logical is ultimately an empirical issue within<br />

<strong>the</strong> general <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> syntactic rules and principles.<br />

See also COMPOSITIONALITY; LOGICAL FORM, ORIGINS OF;<br />

MORPHOLOGY; QUANTIFIERS; SYNTAX-SEMANTICS INTERFACE<br />

—Robert C. May<br />

References<br />

Aoun, J., N. Hornstein, and D. Sportiche (1981). Some aspects <strong>of</strong><br />

wide scope quantification. Journal <strong>of</strong> Linguistic Research 1:<br />

69–95.<br />

Beghelli, F., and T. Stowell (1997). Distributivity and negation:<br />

The syntax <strong>of</strong> each and every. In A. Szabolcsi, Ed., Ways <strong>of</strong><br />

Taking Scope. Dordrecht: Kluwer.<br />

Chomsky, N. (1976). Conditions on rules <strong>of</strong> grammar. Linguistic<br />

Analysis 2: 303–351.<br />

Cooper, R. (1983). Quantification and Syntactic Theory. Dordrecht:<br />

Reidel.<br />

Dowty, D., R. E. Wall, and S. Peters. (1981). Introduction to Montague<br />

Semantics. Dordrecht: Reidel.<br />

Fox, D. (1995). Economy and scope. Natural Language Semantics<br />

3: 283–341.<br />

Higginbotham, J. (1980). Pronouns and bound variables. Linguistic<br />

Inquiry 11: 679–708.<br />

Higginbotham, J., and R. May. (1981). Questions, quantifiers, and<br />

crossing. The Linguistic Review 1: 41–79.<br />

Heim, I. (1982). The Semantics <strong>of</strong> Definite and Indefinite Noun<br />

Phrases. Ph.D. diss., University <strong>of</strong> Massachusetts, Amherst.<br />

Hornstein, N., and A. Weinberg. (1990). The necessity <strong>of</strong> LF. The<br />

Linguistic Review 7: 129–168.<br />

Huang, C.-T. J. (1982). Logical Relations in Chinese and <strong>the</strong> Theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> Grammar. Ph.D. diss., Massachusetts Institute <strong>of</strong> Technology.<br />

Larson, R., and G. Segal. (1995). Knowledge <strong>of</strong> Meaning. Cambridge,<br />

MA: <strong>MIT</strong> Press.<br />

May, R. (1977). The Grammar <strong>of</strong> Quantification. Ph.D. diss., Massachusetts<br />

Institute <strong>of</strong> Technology. (Facsimile edition published<br />

by Garland Publishing, New York, 1991.)<br />

May, R. (1985). Logical Form: Its Structure and Derivation. Cambridge,<br />

MA: <strong>MIT</strong> Press.<br />

May, R. (1989). Interpreting logical form. Linguistics and Philosophy<br />

12: 387–435.<br />

Montague, R. (1974). The proper treatment <strong>of</strong> quantification in<br />

ordinary English. In R. Thomason, Ed., Formal Philosophy:<br />

Selected Papers <strong>of</strong> Richard Montague. New Haven, CT: Yale<br />

University Press.<br />

Partee, B. (1975). Montague grammar and transformational grammar.<br />

Linguistic Inquiry 6: 203–300.<br />

Reinhart, T. (1997). Quantifier scope: How labor is divided<br />

between QR and choice functions. Linguistics and Philosophy<br />

20: 399–467.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>r Readings<br />

Chomsky, N. (1995). The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, MA:<br />

<strong>MIT</strong> Press.<br />

Fiengo, R., and R. May (1994). Indices and Identity. Cambridge,<br />

MA: <strong>MIT</strong> Press.<br />

Frege, G. (1892). On Sense and Reference, trans. by M. Black. In<br />

P. Geach and M. Black, Eds., Translations from <strong>the</strong> Philosophical<br />

Writings <strong>of</strong> Gottlob Frege. Oxford: Blackwell.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!