29.03.2013 Views

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

100 <strong>Rousseau</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Revolution</strong><br />

struggles’ (Marx <strong>and</strong> Engels, 1848). Consequently, the existence of a general<br />

will is claimed to be but an illusion or, more precisely, ideology. That is<br />

to say, the purpose of invocating such a will is to disguise the will of the ruling<br />

class. As Marx <strong>and</strong> Engels put it, the ruling class always ‘represent[s] its<br />

interest as the common interest of all the members of society’ (Marx <strong>and</strong><br />

Engels, 1845).<br />

A slightly different left-wing critique of <strong>Rousseau</strong> is made by the French<br />

philosopher Jacques Rancière. According to Rancière, the problem with<br />

<strong>Rousseau</strong>, as well as with contractualism in general, is that he begins by<br />

initially breaking down the people into individuals, which, in one go, exorcizes<br />

the class war of which politics exists (Rancière, 1998, 79).<br />

On the face of it, such a critique could be considered Marxian. The difference<br />

is, however, that while Marx <strong>and</strong> Engels stress the result of the<br />

social contract, the general will, as opposed to the reality of class struggle,<br />

Rancière denounces the presupposition of this contract, that is, the existence<br />

of independent individuals, free to enter into a contract. Moreover,<br />

Rancière now claims that, although this presupposition too functions as a<br />

veil over class struggle, it also contains an emancipatory potential. In fact,<br />

the presupposition of individual freedom can be used as a tool against<br />

repression:<br />

[With the concept of the social contract], freedom has become peculiar<br />

to individuals as such <strong>and</strong> [ . . . ] the fable of alienation will give rise to the<br />

question of knowing whether <strong>and</strong> under what conditions individuals may<br />

alienate this freedom completely – in a word, it will give rise to the right<br />

of the individual as nonright of the state, the entitlement of anyone at all to<br />

question the state or to serve as proof of its infi delity to its own principle.<br />

(Ibid., 79)<br />

The ‘fable of alienation’ inherent in contractualism is certainly conservating,<br />

but it also opens up the question concerning the conditions of the<br />

legitimacy of this very alienation. As to <strong>Rousseau</strong>, his defi nition of these<br />

conditions is clear <strong>and</strong> radical. True, he dem<strong>and</strong>s, as mentioned, that the<br />

alienation must be total, but the condition therefore is a total recovery of<br />

the alienated rights. The individual can only give up his rights <strong>and</strong> liberty<br />

in so far as he recovers them all in the community. Thus, the goal of the<br />

social contract is ‘to fi nd a form of association [ . . . ] by means of which<br />

each, uniting with all, nevertheless obey only himself <strong>and</strong> remain as free as<br />

before’ (<strong>Rousseau</strong>, 1997e, 49–50).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!