29.03.2013 Views

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Why <strong>Rousseau</strong> Mistrusts <strong>Revolution</strong>s 27<br />

concern is political freedom. Modern peoples attending merely to their<br />

private affairs only pay attention to public matters in an episodic way. This<br />

is both the sign <strong>and</strong> the cause of their political immaturity. It is unlikely for<br />

them to institute, even by way of revolt, a true democracy. We can thus<br />

underst<strong>and</strong> the very harsh judgement levelled against the English who<br />

‘think they are free,’ but ‘who are slaves’ <strong>and</strong> ‘are nothing.’ Even the ‘citizens’<br />

of Geneva who complain about abuses of the Little Council are,<br />

<strong>Rousseau</strong> writes, ‘completely absorbed in their domestic occupations <strong>and</strong><br />

always cool about the rest,’ they ‘consider the public interest only when<br />

their own is being attacked. [ . . . ] Always distracted, always deceived, always<br />

fi xed on other objects, they let themselves be led astray about the most<br />

important one of all, <strong>and</strong> always go looking for the remedy for lack of having<br />

known how to prevent the ill’ (<strong>Rousseau</strong>, 2001, 293).<br />

Here, once again, <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s logic is very close to that of La Boétie, who<br />

refuses to explain tyranny by bad luck, fate or the power of the tyrant.<br />

Tyranny always results from laziness, blindness or the moral corruption of<br />

the people. To bring down the tyrant, according to La Boétie, only one<br />

thing is necessary: that the people want their own freedom: ‘Be resolved to<br />

serve no more <strong>and</strong> you will be free.’ This seems to be such a small thing. But<br />

if tyranny is so common, it may well be that the authentic desire for freedom<br />

is much more diffi cult <strong>and</strong> much more unusual than we might think,<br />

especially if we have not suffi ciently refl ected on the conditions of freedom<br />

in the strong sense.<br />

Can Modern Peoples Actually Attain Freedom?<br />

Should we then consider <strong>Rousseau</strong> as being resigned to the inevitability of<br />

voluntary servitude <strong>and</strong> of seeing no political future for the great European<br />

peoples? I would claim that here, once again, the answer is complicated.<br />

<strong>Rousseau</strong> defi nitely does not share Locke’s anthropological optimism. He<br />

does not agree with Locke’s belief in what <strong>Rousseau</strong> calls in Book IX of The<br />

Confessions <strong>and</strong> in his writings about Saint-Pierre’s projects ‘perfected reason’<br />

[‘la raison perfectionnée’], that is, confi dence in the spontaneous<br />

progress of humankind toward rationality. This idea was adopted by many<br />

of <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s contemporaries <strong>and</strong> illustrated in an exemplary way at the<br />

end of the eighteenth century by Condorcet. But it is also not correct to say<br />

that <strong>Rousseau</strong> is absolutely pessimistic. If he were absolutely pessimistic, he<br />

would have formulated a philosophy of history. He would claim to be thoroughly<br />

knowledgeable about the possibilities of modern humanity <strong>and</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!