29.03.2013 Views

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

22 <strong>Rousseau</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Revolution</strong><br />

etymological sense of someone who recreates a state of war (bellum) within<br />

the civil order. Insurrection against the despot is thus an act of reestablishing<br />

the rule of law, more precisely, an act of vigilante justice. Locke is very<br />

clear about this in several passages from the Second Treatise (Locke, 1988,<br />

§204, §209 <strong>and</strong> §226). He shows at the beginning of this book that, in the<br />

state of nature, private individuals have a right to engage in violence as private<br />

individuals. In the state of nature, such an act of violence is an implementation<br />

of the natural law against the criminal (ibid., §10–13 <strong>and</strong> §20–1).<br />

In other words, for Locke there exists, even in the state of nature, an ability<br />

to judge according to the law <strong>and</strong> to enforce laws, an ability shared by all<br />

men. This is the ability which they then reclaim in situations of tyranny. All<br />

men, or at least most of them, are good judges of the lawful <strong>and</strong> the unlawful.<br />

They can thus take the place of judges <strong>and</strong> the place of positive laws<br />

once civil society is ‘dissolved’. This is just what happens in a revolution<br />

against tyranny. One may suppose, says Locke, that men do not foolishly<br />

take up arms against the sovereign. If they do, it is in judging according to<br />

their conscience <strong>and</strong> in the name of a dem<strong>and</strong> for justice. Here, the<br />

anthropo logical optimism of Locke is very well illustrated: good people are<br />

in the majority; criminals are the exception. Thus when the people rise up,<br />

there is good reason to believe that they are acting in a responsible way <strong>and</strong><br />

in the light of justice (ibid., §223, §225 <strong>and</strong> §230).<br />

It is obvious that <strong>Rousseau</strong> does not share this analysis of revolution <strong>and</strong><br />

this is so for several reasons. To be sure, those who revolt <strong>and</strong> bring down a<br />

tyrant, if they were forced to defend themselves against an oppressive power,<br />

have not necessarily committed a condemnable act. But nothing guarantees<br />

that this legitimate defense will result in the establishment of a more<br />

legitimate authority. Nothing guarantees that a revolt has as its goal the<br />

establishment of the rule of law <strong>and</strong> political liberty. Nothing prevents one<br />

from thinking that this uprising will merely result in the replacement of<br />

one oppression by another. <strong>Rousseau</strong> says it explicitly several times. In The<br />

Letters Written from the Mountain, he writes that ‘in the majority of States<br />

intestine troubles come from a brutalized <strong>and</strong> stupid populace, [ . . . ]<br />

stirred up in secret by skillful troublemakers, invested with some authority<br />

that they want to extend’ (<strong>Rousseau</strong>, 2001, 299). In The Social Contract he<br />

uses history to support this idea, notably seventeenth-century English history.<br />

He twice evokes Oliver Cromwell to this end. In the chapter on ‘civil<br />

religion’ he compares Cromwell to Catiline <strong>and</strong> describes him as ‘an ambitious<br />

man’ <strong>and</strong> ‘a hypocrite’ (<strong>Rousseau</strong>, 1997e, Book IV, chapter 8) who<br />

manipulated the naïve masses. In another chapter, criticizing Cromwell, he<br />

associates him with the Duke of Beaufort, one of the leaders of the Fronde

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!