29.03.2013 Views

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

28 <strong>Rousseau</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Revolution</strong><br />

would declare that it had become structurally incapable of freedom. To<br />

attribute such a philosophy of history to <strong>Rousseau</strong> is a retrospective interpretation.<br />

It is to make him say more than he really did. For <strong>Rousseau</strong>,<br />

contingency <strong>and</strong> unpredictability must be given their full due in history. He<br />

does not believe in any kind of determinism <strong>and</strong> especially not in sociological<br />

determinisms. In Émile he writes: ‘we know not what nature allows us<br />

to be’ (<strong>Rousseau</strong>, 1993b, Book I, 33), <strong>and</strong> in The Social Contract :<br />

The people assembled, it will be said! What a chimera! It is a chimera<br />

today, but it was not so two thous<strong>and</strong> years ago: Have men changed in<br />

nature? The bounds of the possible in moral matters are less narrow than<br />

we think: It is our weaknesses, our vices, our prejudices that constrict<br />

them. Base souls do not believe in great men: vile slaves smile mockingly<br />

at the word freedom. (<strong>Rousseau</strong>, 1997e, Book III, chapter 12)<br />

If human ‘nature’ has remained the same from the time of the Roman<br />

republic to the modern era, this is because in both epochs human nature<br />

harbors misrecognized moral <strong>and</strong> political resources. <strong>Rousseau</strong> says as<br />

much in his text on Pol<strong>and</strong>: ‘When reading ancient history, one believes<br />

oneself transported into another universe <strong>and</strong> among other beings. What<br />

have Frenchmen, Englishmen, Russians, in common with the Romans <strong>and</strong><br />

the Greeks? Almost nothing but their shape. The strong souls of the Romans<br />

<strong>and</strong> the Greeks appear to them to be exaggerations of history.’ But he adds:<br />

‘Yet they did exist, <strong>and</strong> they were humans like ourselves; what keeps us from<br />

being men like them? Our prejudices, our base philosophy <strong>and</strong> the passions<br />

of petty self-interest, concentrated together in all hearts by inept institutions<br />

in which genius never had any share’ (<strong>Rousseau</strong>, 1997a, 79–80). 5<br />

That modern peoples do not, for the most part, know freedom is not due<br />

to some kind of inevitability. It is rather because of a dominant philosophical<br />

<strong>and</strong> cultural tendency, of ‘prejudices’ which portray as a necessity that<br />

which only results from a lack of genius <strong>and</strong> imagination. <strong>Rousseau</strong> thus<br />

reacts against the idea that political freedom, in the strong sense in which<br />

he underst<strong>and</strong>s it, has become outdated <strong>and</strong> is an anachronism to be relegated<br />

to ancient history. In this sense, he is opposed to yet another aspect<br />

of Locke’s thought, one which will be important for later thinkers like<br />

Benjamin Constant <strong>and</strong> Isaiah Berlin. He opposes the idea that democracy<br />

is indeed the destiny of modern peoples, but in a residual, minimalist form,<br />

that of representative democracy in which the people are most often halfasleep.<br />

He thus does not claim that modern peoples would be condemned<br />

to servitude. Evidence of this is found in the interest which he shows in the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!