29.03.2013 Views

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

General Will between Conservation <strong>and</strong> <strong>Revolution</strong> 101<br />

We are dealing here with one of the central paradoxes of <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s<br />

philosophy. The individual must give up the whole of his rights <strong>and</strong> liberty<br />

to the general will in order to maintain the indivisibility of this will. However,<br />

he can legitimately do so only if, in return, he recovers it all, rights<br />

<strong>and</strong> liberty. This central paradox is even more apparent in the fact that,<br />

despite the dem<strong>and</strong> of a total alienation, another central notion in the Social<br />

Contract is that of inalienability. More precisely, it is asserted that, while the<br />

general will is indivisible, the exercise of this will, namely sovereignty, is<br />

inalienable. Now, as hinted at by Rancière, it can be argued that it is exactly<br />

because of this indivisibility that the concept of the general will can be used<br />

in order to legitimate a revolution.<br />

<strong>Revolution</strong>ary Inalienability<br />

<strong>Rousseau</strong>’s philosophical formulation of the notion of inalienability is that<br />

‘sovereignty, since it is nothing but the exercise of the general will, can<br />

never be alienated’ (ibid., 57). A more concrete political formulation is<br />

given a few lines later:<br />

If [ . . . ] the people promises simply to obey, it dissolves itself by this very<br />

act, it loses its quality of being a people; as soon as there is a master, there<br />

is no more sovereign, <strong>and</strong> the body politic is destroyed forthwith. (Ibid.)<br />

Here, the notion of inalienability most clearly implies a radical subversive,<br />

indeed anarchist, conception of the concept of the general will. The ‘body<br />

politic’, that is to say, the general will, does simply not exist if ‘the people’<br />

obeys any ‘master’. Now, one might ask, what would that mean more concretely?<br />

What would a society look like, where nobody obeys any master?<br />

A possible answer can be found in <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s refutation of any kind of<br />

political representation (‘Sovereignty cannot be represented for the same<br />

reason that it cannot be alienated’ (ibid., 114). More technically, the idea is<br />

that, while the executive power can be entrusted to one or more persons,<br />

only the people as such can legitimately exercise the legislative power. The<br />

only legitimate legislative assembly is the whole of the people because ‘the<br />

Sovereign can act only when the people is assembled’ (ibid., 110).<br />

This, however, is obviously impossible. <strong>Rousseau</strong> himself – despite his claim<br />

that ‘the bounds of the possible in moral matters are less narrow than we<br />

think’ (ibid.) – is perfectly aware of the fact that, except in very small states,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!