29.03.2013 Views

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Why <strong>Rousseau</strong> Mistrusts <strong>Revolution</strong>s 29<br />

Corsican <strong>and</strong> Polish insurrections, as well as in his writings which supported<br />

the Genevans who contested the usurpation by the Little Council.<br />

However, one should never ignore how, in these three cases, he carefully<br />

examined the moral <strong>and</strong> cultural situation of the peoples in question before<br />

engaging himself on their side. He writes, the Polish people ‘dares to call<br />

for a government <strong>and</strong> laws, as if it had only just been born. It is in chains,<br />

<strong>and</strong> debates the ways to remain free! It feels in itself the kind of force which<br />

the force of tyranny cannot subjugate’ (ibid., 178). <strong>Rousseau</strong> infers that ‘in<br />

a State like Pol<strong>and</strong> [ . . . ], souls still have great resilience’ (ibid., 218). In<br />

effect, the Poles ‘have just given a forever memorable example’ of ‘the love<br />

of fatherl<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> of freedom animated by the virtues inseparable from that<br />

love’ (ibid., 238). The specifi c nature of the Corsican <strong>and</strong> Polish insurrections,<br />

their organized <strong>and</strong> almost institutional forms, as well as the moral<br />

dispositions to discipline <strong>and</strong> courage manifested, forbid considering these<br />

insurrections as informal <strong>and</strong> anarchic mutinies. Based on his faith in these<br />

initial empirical proofs, <strong>Rousseau</strong> decides to move from theory to practice,<br />

putting his wisdom in the service of political freedom:<br />

I believed myself to be speaking to a people which, while not free of vices,<br />

still had some resilience <strong>and</strong> virtues, <strong>and</strong> on that assumption my project<br />

is a good one. But if Pol<strong>and</strong> is already at the point where everything is<br />

venal <strong>and</strong> rotten to the core, then it is in vain that it seeks to reform its law<br />

<strong>and</strong> to preserve its freedom, it has to renounce doing so <strong>and</strong> bow its head<br />

to the yoke. (Ibid., 242)<br />

Perhaps more than any other author, <strong>Rousseau</strong> exhorts us to change the<br />

world as it now exists. But he does it in his own special way. He brings about<br />

a revolution within the philosophical revolution of modernity. If the revolution<br />

of modern political philosophy is characterized by the belief in the<br />

necessary advent of democracies, <strong>Rousseau</strong> seems to be a conservative<br />

applying the brakes to such enthusiastic ardor. In reality, he is only conservative<br />

in the sense that this belief in democracy necessitates for him, as a<br />

precondition, a moral revolution. Such a contribution to modern revolutionary<br />

thought is, as we might say, anti-modern. It constitutes a reminder<br />

of forgotten lessons taught by the republics of ancient history. The revolution<br />

which <strong>Rousseau</strong> operates within modern revolutionary thought must<br />

thus be understood in the fi rst sense of the word ‘revolution,’ that is to say,<br />

a return to an earlier situation, a closing of a circle. This is the sense in<br />

which his teaching is revolutionary for us moderns. Nurtured by the lessons<br />

of ancient history, he reminds us of what we most often refuse to

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!