29.03.2013 Views

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

102 <strong>Rousseau</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Revolution</strong><br />

it is impossible to gather together the entire ‘people’ on a regular basis in<br />

order to discuss the laws of the republic. Thus, in his proposition for a reformation<br />

of the government of Pol<strong>and</strong>, he admits that ‘the legislative power<br />

cannot show itself as such, <strong>and</strong> can act only by delegation’ (<strong>Rousseau</strong>, 1997a,<br />

200–1). True, <strong>Rousseau</strong> endeavours to limit the power of the Polish diet by<br />

means of imperative m<strong>and</strong>ates <strong>and</strong> a frequent renewal of the representatives<br />

(ibid., 201). The fact remains, however, that he betrays his critique of<br />

political representation as soon as he makes a proposition for a concrete<br />

political structure.<br />

Does this mean that one should simply reject <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s critique of political<br />

representation? From a strictly philosophical point of view, one would<br />

have the right to do so. However, as we are dealing here with the different<br />

uses of <strong>Rousseau</strong>, it should be noted that this critique has actually played a<br />

part in political history despite the impossibility of its institutional implementation.<br />

For instance, as James Swenson points out, this critique was<br />

invoked by different political orators during the entire French <strong>Revolution</strong><br />

(Swenson, 2000, 194–225).<br />

Speaking of insurrection, it is of particular interest that, if also popular<br />

movements during the revolution had a link to <strong>Rousseau</strong>ism, this can be<br />

seen as a direct consequence of <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s critique of representation. As<br />

Swenson puts it, although these movements ‘seldom show the direct imprint<br />

of <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s language’, they ‘can be seen to be largely compatible with the<br />

construction of <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s doctrine that centers on the inalienability of<br />

sovereignty’ (ibid., 217), in particular, the critique of representation. In<br />

fact, <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s assertion that ‘the instant a People gives itself Representatives,<br />

it ceases to be free; it ceases to be’ (<strong>Rousseau</strong>, 1997e, 115) could be<br />

understood less as a defence of a certain political system, namely a system<br />

without representation, than as a de-legitimization of every political system,<br />

given that, as we have seen, no political system without representation is<br />

possible. In other words, <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s critique of political representation can<br />

be used to legitimate any revolt at any time.<br />

It should, therefore, be clear how the concept of the general will can<br />

serve as a legitimation of insurrection: Sovereignty, that is to say, ‘the exercise<br />

of the general will’, is inalienable, <strong>and</strong> therefore political representation<br />

is illegitimate. At the same time, political representation is unavoidable,<br />

<strong>and</strong>, therefore, insurrections are always legitimate. True, such a radical<br />

anarchist reading of <strong>Rousseau</strong> might seem a bit far-fetched; the point is,<br />

however, that it is a possible reading which has operated, although rarely<br />

explicitly, in different collective imaginations.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!