29.03.2013 Views

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

6 <strong>Rousseau</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Revolution</strong><br />

Needless to say, Bachofen’s motivation for making both these moves is not<br />

merely of historical interest but also of concern for contemporary politics.<br />

Even though it might not be polite to interpret one of the contributors to<br />

this anthology (doing to him what he does himself to <strong>Rousseau</strong>), it might<br />

be claimed that Bachofen urges us to fi nd a middle course between two<br />

tendencies in modern French politics <strong>and</strong> especially intellectual life, that is,<br />

on the one h<strong>and</strong>, a Sarkozist liberalist conservatism, <strong>and</strong>, on the other<br />

h<strong>and</strong>, different Marxist or anarchist traditions. In the search for such a<br />

third position, it is obviously an advantage to have <strong>Rousseau</strong> on your side.<br />

In this whole enumeration of different conceptions of <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s relation<br />

to democracy <strong>and</strong> violence, a very recent interpretation of <strong>Rousseau</strong> should<br />

be mentioned, namely, the one briefl y sketched out by Jonathan Israel in<br />

his Radical Enlightenment. Similarly to Bachofen <strong>and</strong> Spitz, Israel claims that<br />

<strong>Rousseau</strong>’s place in a specifi c republican tradition has been overlooked,<br />

<strong>and</strong> that he does thus not belong to a Lockean tradition of natural right.<br />

However, the republicanism referred to by Israel is not the one referred to<br />

by Bachofen <strong>and</strong> Spitz, that is, the Pocockian ‘classical’ or ‘Atlantic’ republicanism,<br />

but instead a ‘democratic republicanism’ inspired by Spinoza, the<br />

so-called radical Enlightenment that, together with materialism <strong>and</strong> anticlericalism,<br />

propagated radically egalitarian ideas. Thus, according to Israel,<br />

<strong>Rousseau</strong> did not really, as in Bachofen’s <strong>and</strong> Spitz’s view, render a tradition<br />

more democratic than it was, but rather inferred his radically democratic<br />

views from ideas already inherent to the radical strain of the Enlightenment,<br />

ideas to which, moreover, he was also sometimes opposed:<br />

Any proper appreciation of <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s role <strong>and</strong> greatness has to concede<br />

that his thought springs from a long, <strong>and</strong> almost obsessive dialogue with the<br />

radical ideas of the past – in many cases as fi ltered through the mind of his<br />

former comrade Diderot (Israel, 2002, 718).<br />

And then, just adding to the complexity of both <strong>Rousseau</strong> himself <strong>and</strong> his<br />

reception, Israel, in a later work, describes how ‘<strong>Rousseau</strong>’s political goals<br />

all tended to an agenda that the radical philosophes [ . . . ] in varying degrees<br />

deplored <strong>and</strong> consciously strove to avoid’ (Israel, 2010, 63–4), not least his<br />

alleged preference for direct democracy.<br />

Philosophy <strong>and</strong> Political Change<br />

The question of philosophy’s part in social or political change is a controversial<br />

<strong>and</strong> contested debate. Philosophers, historians <strong>and</strong> social scientists<br />

debate the interrelationship between ideas, structures <strong>and</strong> societael

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!