29.03.2013 Views

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Introduction 5<br />

we fi nd two versions of this applied to <strong>Rousseau</strong>. The fi rst position portrays<br />

<strong>Rousseau</strong> as anti-democratic, perhaps even totalitarian, <strong>and</strong> his political<br />

project, especially the notion of the general will, opens up for or legitimizes<br />

violent despotic rule. This is the conservative, Burkean reading of <strong>Rousseau</strong><br />

by, for instance, Jacob Talmon in his 1952 book The Origins of Totalitarian<br />

Democracy. In the other position, <strong>Rousseau</strong>, according to Blaise Bachofen,<br />

represents a certain republican conception of democracy which, in opposition<br />

to the liberal tradition, especially Locke, is sceptical of violent popular<br />

uprisings <strong>and</strong> revolutions. More specifi cally, Bachofen claims that <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s<br />

republican conception of democracy is more concerned about ‘the moral<br />

precondition for freedom’, that is, a long <strong>and</strong> diffi cult education of the<br />

people by which a sum of particular wills is converted into a general will,<br />

than about the act of liberation from tyranny. ‘The free people is not – or is<br />

not only – a people who frees itself from subjugation by a violent act. The<br />

free people is the one who is morally capable of freedom, who is educated<br />

towards freedom.’ (Bachofen, Chapter 1).<br />

Whether one or another of these many readings of <strong>Rousseau</strong> is the right<br />

one should not be determined here. From the point of view of intellectual<br />

history, however, Bachofen’s interpretation is interesting in so far as it –<br />

partly inspired by another French scholar in political philosophy, Jean-<br />

Fabien Spitz (1995, 341–465) – explicitly links <strong>Rousseau</strong> to the so-called<br />

republican tradition in Western political thought (Bachofen, 2002, 15).<br />

This tradition has had a revival in the last decades <strong>and</strong> is represented by<br />

neo-republican scholars such as J. G. A. Pocock (1975), Quentin Skinner<br />

(1999), Phillip Pettit (1997) <strong>and</strong> Maurizio Viroli (2002). In this mainly<br />

anglophone tradition, however, <strong>Rousseau</strong> has most often been either forgotten<br />

or considered as identical with some kind of tyrannical populist majoritarianism<br />

(‘<strong>Rousseau</strong> is probably responsible for having given currency to<br />

[ . . . ] a populist view’, (Pettit, 1997, 30)) opposed to the balanced spirit of<br />

true republicanism.<br />

On the other h<strong>and</strong>, by showing how <strong>Rousseau</strong> does in fact belong to the<br />

republican tradition, Bachofen seems to makes a double move. On the one<br />

h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s democratic theory is made republican (that is, republican in<br />

the moderate sense given to this word by Pocock, Skinner, Pettit, Viroli,<br />

etc.) <strong>and</strong> is thus being differentiated from other conceptions of democracy<br />

put forward by socialists, radicals <strong>and</strong> revolutionaries who traditionally<br />

claim to have <strong>Rousseau</strong> on their side. On the other h<strong>and</strong>, the republican<br />

tradition is made more democratic than it is when presented by the mentioned<br />

neo-republicans who most often do not, as <strong>Rousseau</strong>, regard popular<br />

sovereignty as a condition of the legitimacy of any political society.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!