29.03.2013 Views

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

Rousseau and Revolution

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

General Will between Conservation <strong>and</strong> <strong>Revolution</strong> 103<br />

Now, it could be maintained that <strong>Rousseau</strong> was actually aware of the possibility<br />

of such an anarchist reading. Thus, after having claimed, as quoted<br />

above, that ‘as soon as there is a master, there is no more sovereign’, he<br />

makes a restriction:<br />

This is not to say that the comm<strong>and</strong>s of the chiefs may not be taken for<br />

general wills as long as the sovereign is free to oppose them <strong>and</strong> does not<br />

do so. In such a case the people’s consent has to be presumed from universal<br />

silence. (Ibid., 57–8)<br />

This idea is quite sophisticated <strong>and</strong> seems both to render the anarchist<br />

reading more likely <strong>and</strong> to bring it nearer to a somewhat practicable kind<br />

of politics. While <strong>Rousseau</strong> maintains that it is always legitimate for the<br />

people to oppose a political decision made by a political leader, for instance,<br />

a representative, he underscores that this does not mean that every such<br />

decision is illegitimate. In fact, as long as the people do not revolt against<br />

such decisions, they should be considered as legitimate. However, as the<br />

absence of revolt can obviously be due to repression, <strong>Rousseau</strong> adds that<br />

the people must be ‘free to oppose’ a decision or a comm<strong>and</strong>, that is to say,<br />

free to revolt. It thus seems that, as a correlate to what is here called (deliberately<br />

anachronistically) the ‘radical anarchist’ reading of <strong>Rousseau</strong>, it is<br />

possible to construct a more ‘moderate’ or ‘realistic’ anarchist reading.<br />

This reading too, however, contains several problems. In particular, it<br />

should be asked what is actually meant when ‘a people’ is said to be free to<br />

revolt? Does it mean that the people have the right to revolt? Such an interpretation<br />

seems contradictory, revolts being by defi nition illegal. Nevertheless,<br />

<strong>Rousseau</strong> might have thought of such a solution. As a matter of fact,<br />

when discussing the Constitution of Pol<strong>and</strong>, he praises a specifi c law that<br />

could be understood as a legitimation of revolt. This law provides that<br />

under certain circumstances it is possible to create a so-called confederative<br />

diet where for instance the normal right of veto does not apply, <strong>and</strong>, when<br />

<strong>Rousseau</strong> states that ‘this federative form [ . . . ] strikes me as a masterpiece<br />

of politics’ (<strong>Rousseau</strong>, 1997a, 219–20), it is, according to Sven Stelling-<br />

Michaud, exactly because he ‘sees in this practice a legal form of insurrection’<br />

(Stelling-Michaud, 1978, 1778).<br />

As mentioned, popular uprisings during the French <strong>Revolution</strong> were often<br />

if not explicitly referring to <strong>Rousseau</strong>’s critique of representation, then compatible<br />

with it. Other initiatives during the revolution in fact pointed towards<br />

this legalization or institutionalization of revolts that <strong>Rousseau</strong> saw in the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!