15.08.2013 Views

Hollywood Utopia

Hollywood Utopia

Hollywood Utopia

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

190 <strong>Hollywood</strong> <strong>Utopia</strong><br />

notion of a pristine wilderness’ or the idea of a ‘limitless fully immersive<br />

cyberspace’ (Robins 1996: 93). Such spatial analysis falls into the trap of<br />

positioning all abstract notions of space into the same dimension of ‘cognitive<br />

mapping’ mentioned previously, thereby demeaning the more concrete ecological<br />

appreciation of space as a constituent of interactive organisms, including human.<br />

Criticism becomes trapped in an ethereal cyberspace where ‘man can play God’<br />

but without having to cope with the ethics of responsibility or the chaotic fluidity<br />

of our ‘natural’ spatial eco-system.<br />

The importance of spatial analysis can perhaps best be understood with reference<br />

to Kant’s concept of the ‘sublime’ and the ‘pleasure’ achieved through human<br />

communion with the environment. Kant cogently affirms a conventional romantic<br />

sensibility when he asserts that while ‘beauty’ can be regarded as mere ‘restful<br />

contemplation’, the ‘sublime’ in contrast creates an ‘intellectual feeling’ and makes<br />

us ‘feel moved’. Lyotard nevertheless appears to turn Kant’s theory upside down,<br />

exposing ‘its strange non-connectivity to nature’. The sublime, on the whole, gives<br />

‘no indication of anything final in nature itself, but only the possible employment<br />

of our intuitions of it. It is ignorant of nature . . .’ (Lyotard cited in Haber 1994:<br />

139).<br />

Lyotard goes on to associate the sublime with the ‘unrepresentable’ which is<br />

beyond the mastery of naming and which prompts artistic (and by implication<br />

intellectual and social) experiment. Lyotard regards the Kantian sublime as being<br />

closely bound up with the essence of modernity. The modernist sublime, which has<br />

been explored in earlier chapters, following this line of argument, is essentially<br />

nostalgic and its form ‘continues to offer to the reader or viewer, matter for solace<br />

or pleasure’ (Lyotard 1984: 340).<br />

Whereas for Lyotard the postmodern (avant-gardist), sublime<br />

puts forward the unpresentable in presentation itself; that which denies itself the<br />

solace of good forms, the consensus of a taste which would make it possible to share<br />

collectively the nostalgia for the unattainable; that which searches for new presentations,<br />

not in order to enjoy them but in order to impart a stronger sense of the unpresentable<br />

(ibid.)<br />

Lyotard specifically focuses on what he sees as the postmodernist inability to<br />

represent, which, according to Broderick, now ‘surpasses our power to represent<br />

and pitches us into a sort of Gothic rapture’ (Broderick 1995: 104). Bertens<br />

usefully suggests, however, that both modern and postmodernist aesthetics remain<br />

preoccupied with notions of the sublime and are equally concerned with the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!