07.01.2013 Views

Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology - uncopy

Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology - uncopy

Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology - uncopy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

as any kind of art; it can’t claim a special identity, an existence for its own sake as a medium. If<br />

it does it will end up like lithography and etching.”In other words, for painting to be “real,”<br />

its problems must be problems of art. But neither painting nor sculpture is synonymous with<br />

art, though they may be used as art. To confuse the appearance of painting with art is to mistake<br />

the identity of a class of things with art itself (which of course has no appearance). Accepting<br />

such a basis for one’s art entails advocating an a priori concept of what art can be and how it<br />

should appear.<br />

The critical role sustaining the function of Formalist art depends on the Formalist presenting<br />

the “experience”and the critics presenting the “ideas.”Such artists appear to have<br />

abandoned responsibility for their ideas in order to allow the critic to analyze (or interpret) the<br />

experience provided by the art. In addition, a whole hierarchy of roles is being maintained<br />

through this attitude; for example, galleries, museum officials, critics etc., who do not want<br />

art to change its traditional identity, depend for their vocation on the institutionalization of<br />

experience-as-art, aesthetics-as-art, and even investments-as-art. As such, art functions through<br />

polite and cultured “experiences”and this function is governed by an a priori concept of what<br />

art should be. It is precisely such a regulated function that <strong>Conceptual</strong> <strong>Art</strong>’s “strict and radical<br />

extreme”seeks to usurp.<br />

During the twentieth century, all innovations in art have been conceptual; to mistake as<br />

such the changing of say hard-edge to soft-edge is to have a peculiarly telescoped view of one’s<br />

“language”and to confuse art’s function with a kind of rearrangement of furniture. Since Cubism<br />

and Malevich’s Black Square, through Reinhardt’s Invisible Paintings, there has been an<br />

obsessive desire to abstract; that is, artists have wanted to remove their art from “the green<br />

world of flesh and bones”and purge it of anything that was recognizable (be it flying angels or<br />

abstract imagery). Anything in art that was not strictly art was progressively eliminated. <strong>Conceptual</strong><br />

<strong>Art</strong> can be seen within this tradition; not only does it remove morphological significance<br />

as art, but it isolates “the art”from the form of presentation altogether.<br />

The influence of Minimalism2 on the thinking of certain of the <strong>Conceptual</strong> artists has<br />

been to bring about an awareness that the art-object is not self-supporting. One of Andre’s<br />

Floors is art in the Dwan Gallery, but not necessarily if placed on a sidewalk; i.e. this object,<br />

lacking an identifiable morphology, now depends upon its context to be seen as art. 3 One such<br />

context is the “linguistic support”that the art-society provides for its art-works; and through<br />

such supports we identify an art-work as an art-work. In other words, “what is singled out<br />

depends entirely upon how one does one’s singling out.”<strong>Conceptual</strong> <strong>Art</strong> shifts the focus from<br />

what is said through the language to an investigation of the language itself; 4 it expands the art<br />

ian burn conceptual art as art 189

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!