07.01.2013 Views

Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology - uncopy

Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology - uncopy

Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology - uncopy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

to be given primacy over the visual qualities identified by the linguistic entity, or was the perceptual<br />

experience of the visual, formal, and chromatic element anterior to its mere denomination<br />

by language?<br />

Clearly this “mapping of the linguistic onto the perceptual” was not arguing in favor of<br />

“the idea”—or linguistic primacy—or the definition of the work of art as an analytic proposition.<br />

Quite to the contrary, the permutational character of the work suggested that the viewer/<br />

reader systematically perform all the visual and textual options the painting’s parameters allowed<br />

for. This included an acknowledgment of the painting’s central, square element: a spatial<br />

void that revealed the underlying wall surface as the painting’s architectural support in actual<br />

space, thereby suspending the reading of the painting between architectural structure and linguistic<br />

definition.<br />

Rather than privileging one over the other, LeWitt’s work (in its dialogue with Jasper<br />

Johns’s legacy of paradox) insisted on forcing the inherent contradictions of the two spheres<br />

(that of the perceptual experience and that of the linguistic experience) into the highest possible<br />

relief. Unlike Frank Stella’s response to Johns, which forced modernist self-referentiality one<br />

step further into the ultimate cul de sac of its positivist convictions (his notorious statement<br />

“what you see is what you see” would attest to that just as much as the development of his<br />

later work), 4 Sol LeWitt’s dialogue (with both Johns and Stella, and ultimately, of course, with<br />

Greenberg) developed a dialectical position with regard to the positivist legacy.<br />

In contrast to Stella, his work now revealed that the modernist compulsion for empiricist<br />

self-reflexiveness not only originated in the scientific positivism which is the founding logic of<br />

capitalism (undergirding its industrial forms of production just as much as its science and<br />

theory), but that, for an artistic practice that internalized this positivism by insisting on a<br />

purely empiricist approach to vision, there would be a final destiny. This destiny would be to<br />

aspire to the condition of tautology.<br />

It is not surprising, then, that when LeWitt formulated his second text on <strong>Conceptual</strong><br />

<strong>Art</strong>—in his “Sentences on <strong>Conceptual</strong> <strong>Art</strong>” from the spring of 1969—the first sentence should<br />

programmatically state the radical difference between the logic of scientific production and<br />

that of aesthetic experience:<br />

1 — <strong>Conceptual</strong> artists are mystics rather than rationalists. They leap to conclusions that logic cannot<br />

reach.<br />

2 — Rational judgments repeat rational judgments.<br />

3 — Irrational judgments lead to new experience. 5<br />

benjamin h. d. buchloh conceptual art 1962–1969 517

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!