07.01.2013 Views

Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology - uncopy

Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology - uncopy

Conceptual Art: A Critical Anthology - uncopy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

544<br />

is probably not worth considering as art. And <strong>Conceptual</strong> <strong>Art</strong> is nothing if there is no power<br />

to its claim to be occupying the space of art. What I mean by this is that <strong>Conceptual</strong> <strong>Art</strong> is not<br />

art at all unless its objects are intentional objects under some description; and it is not art of<br />

any critical interest unless it enforces recognition of a transformation amongst that range of<br />

descriptions under which something may be seen as intentional.<br />

There are of course those who would claim that the radicalism of <strong>Conceptual</strong> <strong>Art</strong> lay<br />

not in its occupation but rather in its displacement of the space of art—a displacement effected<br />

precisely by breaking down the barriers between the aesthetic and the political and between<br />

the over-specialized high arts and the more notionally “popular” (through in fact simply more<br />

readily distributable) arts of publicity. From this point of view the concern for quality is seen<br />

as a form of abnegation of the requirement of effectiveness. This argument is all very well, but<br />

the works at issue tend either to establish themselves in a thoroughly conventional world of art<br />

or to be absorbed without aesthetic remainder into the larger world they purport to invade.<br />

(<strong>Art</strong>ists cited in support of such arguments include Burgin, Haacke, Holzer and Kruger.) In<br />

the first case the works thus represented are subject to whatever institutional or fashionable<br />

criteria may happen to prevail. In the second case they do indeed put themselves beyond the<br />

concerns of qualitative judgement, but only by failing to be of interest as intentional objects<br />

under some critically significant description. In neither case do they offer any novel address or<br />

alternative to the requirement of depth in art. This is to say that they do nothing to resist the<br />

form of manipulative agency associated with the image of the beholder.<br />

If a case is to be made for the art-historical significance of <strong>Conceptual</strong> <strong>Art</strong>, it seems clear<br />

that it will not be enough either to reproduce the protocols of late-Modernist aesthetics under<br />

a new Post-Minimalist disguise, or to replace judgement with claims for non-cognitive effectiveness.<br />

The case will have to be one which, while it resists the conventions of quality associated<br />

with the ideology of Modernism, nevertheless admits the possibility—and difficulty—of evaluating<br />

works of <strong>Conceptual</strong> <strong>Art</strong> as intentional objects under a range of relevant descriptions.<br />

And this will entail some assessment of the readings—and not simply of the categorymistakes—which<br />

works of <strong>Conceptual</strong> <strong>Art</strong> avail. The demand for intelligent readings rather<br />

than involuntary responses is still instinct in those works of <strong>Conceptual</strong> <strong>Art</strong> which have remained<br />

interesting (and in that sense “stood the test of time”). That demand should not now<br />

be replaced or forgotten in the name of some automatic art-historical authenticity.<br />

This is not a plea for the restoration of connoisseurship on some already-discredited<br />

basis (such as the self-serving fiction that art speaks for itself to the innately sensitive). Rather<br />

it is to affirm that need for interpretative reading (Verstehen) which was implicitly asserted in

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!