07.08.2013 Views

Unfitness to Plead Consultation Responses - Law Commission ...

Unfitness to Plead Consultation Responses - Law Commission ...

Unfitness to Plead Consultation Responses - Law Commission ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

The assumption that has been made is that assessments of rationality refer <strong>to</strong> the<br />

content of the decision rather than the process by which the decision was<br />

reached (see 3.51 for the distinction). The content of the decision necessarily<br />

depends on the decision‐maker’s interests and values. So <strong>to</strong> base an assessment<br />

of capacity on the content of the decision would threaten the right <strong>to</strong> self‐<br />

determination (3.48); the right <strong>to</strong> pursue one’s own interests and values. Instead,<br />

the CP proposes, I think appropriately, that evaluations of decision‐making<br />

capacity should “focus on the process of understanding and reasoning” that gives<br />

rise <strong>to</strong> the decision (3.51). The CP notes, however, that “This is not <strong>to</strong> say … that<br />

the<br />

rationality or otherwise of a decision is irrelevant.” In other words, this is not<br />

<strong>to</strong> say the content of the decision is irrelevant.<br />

The understanding of “rationality” adopted in the CP is consistent, I believe, with<br />

the understanding of the term most widely adopted in discussions of mental<br />

capacity in English law. However, this usage diverges from the dominant use of<br />

the term in psychology and philosophy, where “rationality” is used <strong>to</strong> refer <strong>to</strong><br />

both the process and the content of decisions. The former is often called<br />

“procedural rationality” and the latter “substantive rationality”. And of the two,<br />

procedural rationality is generally considered the most basic use of the term. I<br />

have<br />

explored these ideas more fully in a paper that is currently under review<br />

(Craigie & Coram, under review).<br />

While I believe the CP’s use of the term should be made explicit, it is my view<br />

that this use of the term is justifiable given its consistency with the established<br />

use<br />

of the term in English medical law. I note, however, that this usage has been<br />

criticized in the context of US medical law:<br />

“Some courts have shied away from embracing this standard because of an<br />

apparent confusion regarding interpretation of the term irrational. A decision<br />

sometimes has been called irrational merely because the patient’s choice was<br />

unconventional … In contrast, the “irrationality” <strong>to</strong> which this standard properly<br />

refers<br />

pertains <strong>to</strong> illogic in the processing of information, not the choice that<br />

eventually<br />

is made” (Appelbaum & Grisso 1995: 110)<br />

References:<br />

P.S Appelbaum & T. Grisso. (1995) The MacArthur Treatment Competence Study I:<br />

mental<br />

illness and competence <strong>to</strong> consent <strong>to</strong> treatment. <strong>Law</strong> and Human Behaviour<br />

19(2): 105‐126.<br />

Craigie, J. & Coram, A. (under review) Irrationality, Capacity and Neuroscience, In: Legal<br />

Responsibility and Neuroscience, Nicole A Vincent<br />

(ed.) OUP series "Neuroscience, <strong>Law</strong>,<br />

and Philosophy" (series eds.: Lynn Nadel, Fred Schauer, and Walter<br />

Sinnott‐Armstrong).<br />

A draft can be downloaded from this page:<br />

h<br />

ttp://www.kcl.ac.uk/law/people/researchcentres/jcraigie.aspx

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!