13.06.2015 Views

Kiefer C. Quantum gravity

Kiefer C. Quantum gravity

Kiefer C. Quantum gravity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

96 PARAMETRIZED AND RELATIONAL SYSTEMS<br />

in this connection that in 1905 Henri Poincaré argued for a definition of time<br />

that makes the equations of motion assume their simplest form. He writes 6<br />

Time must be defined in such a way that the equations of mechanics are as simple as<br />

possible. In other words, there is no way to measure time that is more true than any<br />

other; the one that is usually adopted is only more convenient.<br />

It is, however, a fact that the choice (3.109) is not only distinguished because<br />

then the equations of motion (3.106) take their simplest form but also because<br />

only such a choice will ensure that the various clocks of (approximately isolated)<br />

subsystems march in step, since ∑ k (T k +V k )= ∑ k E k = 0 (Barbour 1994). The<br />

only truly isolated system is the universe as a whole and to determine time it is<br />

(in principle) necessary to monitor the whole universe. In practice this is done<br />

even when atomic clocks are employed, for example, in the determination of the<br />

pulse arrival times from binary pulsars (Damour and Taylor 1991).<br />

In this approach, the inertial frame and absolute time of Newtonian mechanics<br />

are constructed from observations through the minimization of the kinetic<br />

energy and the above choice of τ. One could call this a Leibnizian or Machian<br />

point of view. The operational time defined by (3.109) corresponds to the notion<br />

of ‘ephemeris time’ used in astronomy. That time must be defined such that the<br />

equations of motion be simple was already known by Ptolemy (Barbour 1989).<br />

His theory of eclipses only took a simple form if sidereal time (defined by the<br />

rotation of the heavens, i.e. the rotation of the Earth) is used. This choice corresponds<br />

to a ‘uniform flow of time’.<br />

Time-reparametrization invariant systems have already been discussed in Section<br />

3.1.1 in connection with the parametrized non-relativistic particle. In contrast<br />

to there, however, no absolute time is present here and the theory relies<br />

exclusively on observational elements.<br />

A formal analogy of the action (3.105) is given by Jacobi’s action 7 in classical<br />

mechanics (Barbour 1986; Lanczos 1986; Brown and York 1989),<br />

∫<br />

S J = ds √ E − V , (3.110)<br />

where E is the total energy, and s parametrizes the paths in configuration space,<br />

ds 2 ≡<br />

n∑<br />

m k dx k dx k .<br />

k=1<br />

Writing ds =ṡdτ, onegetsṡ = √ 2T ;ifE = 0, then, Jacobi’s action is proportional<br />

to the action (3.105).<br />

6 ‘Le temps doit être défini de telle façon que les équations de la mécanique soient aussi<br />

simples que possible. En d’autres termes, il n’y a pas une manière de mesurer le temps qui<br />

soit plus vraie qu’ une autre; celle qui est généralement adoptée est seulement plus commode.’<br />

(Poincaré 1970)<br />

7 There is a close analogy of this formulation with Fermat’s principle of least time in geometrical<br />

optics.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!