13.06.2015 Views

Kiefer C. Quantum gravity

Kiefer C. Quantum gravity

Kiefer C. Quantum gravity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

106 HAMILTONIAN FORMULATION OF GENERAL RELATIVITY<br />

4.2.1 The canonical variables<br />

The Hamiltonian formalism starts from the choice of a configuration variable<br />

and the definition of its momentum. Since the latter requires a time coordinate<br />

(‘p = ∂L/∂ ˙q’), one must cast GR in a form where it exhibits a ‘distinguished’<br />

time.Thisisachievedbyfoliating the space–time described by (M,g)intoa<br />

set of three-dimensional space-like hypersurfaces Σ t ; cf. also Section 3.3. The<br />

covariance of GR is preserved by allowing for the possibility to consider all<br />

feasible foliations of this type.<br />

This is not only of relevance for quantization (which is our motivation here),<br />

but also for important applications in the classical theory. For example, numerical<br />

relativity needs a description in terms of foliations in order to describe the<br />

dynamical evolution of events, for example, the coalescence of black holes and<br />

their emission of gravitational waves (Baumgarte and Shapiro 2003).<br />

As a necessary condition we want to demand that (M,g) be globally hyperbolic,<br />

that is, it possesses a Cauchy surface Σ (an ‘instant of time’) on which<br />

initial data can be described to determine uniquely the whole space–time, see<br />

for example, Wald (1984) or Hawking and Ellis (1973) for details. In such cases,<br />

the classical initial value formulation makes sense, and the Hamiltonian form of<br />

GR can be constructed. The occurrence of naked singularities is prohibited by<br />

this assumption.<br />

An important theorem states that for a globally hyperbolic space–time (M,g)<br />

there exists a global ‘time function’ f such that each surface f = constant is a<br />

Cauchy surface; therefore, M can be foliated into Cauchy hypersurfaces, and its<br />

topology is a direct product,<br />

M ∼ = R × Σ . (4.38)<br />

The topology of space–time is thus fixed. This may be a reasonable assumption in<br />

the classical theory, since topology change is usually connected with singularities<br />

or closed time-like curves. In the quantum theory, topology change may be a<br />

viable option and its absence in the formalism could be a possible weakness of<br />

the canonical approach. 8 Nevertheless, the resulting quantum theory is general<br />

enough to cope with many of the interesting situations.<br />

One therefore starts with performing a foliation of space–time into Cauchy<br />

surfaces Σ t ,witht denoting the global time function (‘3+1 decomposition’). The<br />

corresponding vector field (‘flow of time’) is denoted by t µ ,obeyingt µ ∇ µ t =1.<br />

The relation between infinitesimally neighboured hypersurfaces is the same as<br />

shown in Fig. 3.1. 9 The space–time metric g µν induces a three-dimensional metric<br />

on each Σ t according to<br />

h µν = g µν + n µ n ν , (4.39)<br />

where n µ denotes again the unit normal to Σ t ,withn µ n µ = −1.<br />

8 A more general formulation allowing topology change to occur in principle is the pathintegral<br />

approach of Section 2.2.<br />

9 The vector field t µ was called Ẋ µ in Fig. 3.1 and the relation (3.74).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!