13.06.2015 Views

Kiefer C. Quantum gravity

Kiefer C. Quantum gravity

Kiefer C. Quantum gravity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

310 INTERPRETATION<br />

the quantum entanglement between apparatus and environment. Under ordinary<br />

macroscopic situations, decoherence occurs on an extremely short timescale,<br />

giving the impression of an instantaneous collapse or a ‘quantum jump’.<br />

Recent experiments were able to demonstrate the continuous emergence of classical<br />

properties in mesoscopic systems (Hornberger et al. 2003; Joos et al. 2003).<br />

Therefore, one would never ever be able to observe a weird superposition such<br />

as Schrödinger’s cat, because the information about this superposition would<br />

almost instantaneously be delocalized into unobservable correlations with the<br />

environment, resulting in an apparent collapse for the cat state.<br />

The interaction with the environment distinguishes the local basis with respect<br />

to which classical properties (unobservability of interferences) hold. This<br />

‘pointer basis’ must obey the condition of robustness, that is, it must keep its<br />

classical appearance over the relevant time-scales; cf. Zurek (2003). Classical<br />

properties are thus not intrinsic to any object, but only defined by their interaction<br />

with other degrees of freedom. In simple (Markovian, i.e. local in time)<br />

situations, the pointer states are given by localized Gaussian states (Diósi and<br />

<strong>Kiefer</strong> 2000). They are, in particular, relevant for the localization of macroscopic<br />

objects.<br />

The ubiquitous occurrence of decoherence renders the interpretational problem<br />

of quantum theory at present largely a ‘matter of taste’ (Zeh 1994). Provided<br />

one adopts a realistic interpretation without additional variables, 1 the alternatives<br />

would be to have either an Everett interpretation or the assumption of a<br />

collapse for the total system (including the environment). The latter would have<br />

to entail an explicit modification of quantum theory, since one would have to introduce<br />

non-linear or stochastic terms into the Schrödinger equation in order to<br />

achieve this goal. The Everett interpretation assumes that all components of the<br />

full quantum state exist and are real. Decoherence produces robust macroscopic<br />

branches, one of which corresponds to the observed world. Interferences with the<br />

other branches are suppressed, so decoherence readily explains the observation<br />

of an apparent collapse of the wave function, independent of whether there is a<br />

real collapse for the total system or not. The question is thus whether one applies<br />

Ockham’s razor 2 to the equations or the intuition (Zeh 1994): either one has to<br />

complicate the formalism in order to have just one macroscopic branch or one<br />

retains the linear structure of quantum theory and has to accept the existence<br />

of ‘many worlds’.<br />

10.1.2 Decoherence in quantum cosmology<br />

In this subsection, we investigate the question: how can one understand the classical<br />

appearance of global space–time variables such as the radius (scale factor)<br />

of the universe? If decoherence is the fundamental process, we have to identify a<br />

‘system’ and an ‘environment’. More precisely, we have to differentiate between<br />

relevant and irrelevant variables. All degrees of freedom exist, of course, within<br />

1 The Bohm theory would be an example for a realistic approach with additional variables.<br />

2 ‘Pluralitas non est ponenda sine necessitate’.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!