12.07.2015 Views

PACIFIC WORLD - The Institute of Buddhist Studies

PACIFIC WORLD - The Institute of Buddhist Studies

PACIFIC WORLD - The Institute of Buddhist Studies

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Eckel: Defining a Usable Past 73What is the source <strong>of</strong> these paradoxes, and how can they be resolved,if they can be resolved at all? In my discussion <strong>of</strong> the Primal Vow, Imentioned the <strong>Buddhist</strong> paradox <strong>of</strong> identity. This is a paradox that anystudents <strong>of</strong> Buddhism confront when they begin to ask questions abouttraditional <strong>Buddhist</strong> views <strong>of</strong> reality. If everything changes and there is nopermanent self, who is it who acts? If there is no self, who remembersyesterday’s events or the events <strong>of</strong> a previous life? And if there is no self,who practices the path and hopes some day to achieve nirvana? <strong>The</strong> sameproblems apply to the concept <strong>of</strong> the Buddha, but with even greater force,since a buddha is a being who has perfectly realized and perfectly embodiedthe awareness <strong>of</strong> no-self. If buddhahood is defined as the awareness <strong>of</strong>no-self or (in Mahåyåna terms) emptiness, how can a buddha choose oneaction over another? If everything is empty, how can the practices that leadfrom a bodhisattva to a buddha make any sense? <strong>The</strong>re are many ways tounderstand the idea <strong>of</strong> no-self, <strong>of</strong> course, but the problems remain remarkablyconstant in different schools <strong>of</strong> <strong>Buddhist</strong> thought. <strong>Buddhist</strong>s want tobe free from attributing any permanent identity to things, yet they alsowant to count on a predictable sequence <strong>of</strong> events, along with the possibilitythat whatever they do today will bear some fruit tomorrow, no matterhow much they may have changed.Karl Potter gave a useful, if rather abstract, explanation <strong>of</strong> this dilemmawhen he said that every Indian philosophical school has to avoid twoproblems: fatalism and skepticism. 54 Fatalism means that things willalways be the way they are and nothing can be done to change them.Skepticism means that, while things may change, there is nothing I can doto change them or benefit from the change. You might say that a fatalistthinks that the chain <strong>of</strong> causation is too tight and everything is predetermined.A skeptic thinks the chain is too loose and actions have no predictableeffect. To avoid these two problems, an Indian philosopher has toshow how things can be free to change but also how the change can besufficiently predictable that a person can do something today and hope toget some result from it tomorrow. In other words, there has to be anelement <strong>of</strong> freedom in a system and also an element <strong>of</strong> predictability. Ifeither freedom or predictability is missing, it is impossible to makechoices that have any meaning, from buying the morning newspaper toseeking nirvana.Given this set <strong>of</strong> choices, the classical <strong>Buddhist</strong> tradition opted decisivelyfor freedom. <strong>Buddhist</strong> thinkers said that reality ultimately involvedno self. By no self they meant not only that there was no continuous realityfrom one moment to the next, but, in the more radical interpretation <strong>of</strong> theMahåyåna, no reality even in the individual moments themselves. Heraclitusmay have said that you cannot step into the same river twice, but thephilosophers <strong>of</strong> the Mahåyåna took the point a step further and said thatyou cannot step into the same river once. This choice, <strong>of</strong> course, left the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!