30.08.2015 Views

CONSCIOUSNESS

Download - Center for Consciousness Studies - University of Arizona

Download - Center for Consciousness Studies - University of Arizona

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

2. Neuroscience 117<br />

is 3 times larger than any previous brain network, and contains sub-networks corresponding to<br />

classical corticocortical, corticosubcortical, and subcortico-subcortical white matter fiber systems.<br />

The degree distribution of the network is consistent with an exponential distribution. We<br />

discover two remarkable bridges between brain’s structure and function via network-theoretic<br />

analysis. First, prefrontal cortex contains a lion’s share of topologically central regions. Second,<br />

there exists a tightly integrated core circuit, spanning premotor cortex, prefrontal cortex,<br />

temporal lobe, parietal lobe, thalamus, basal ganglia, cingulate cortex, insula, and visual cortex,<br />

that contains both the task-positive and task-negative networks and may be the substrate<br />

for higher cognition and consciousness. PL4<br />

150 The Frames of Consciousness: The Role of Motivation and Emotion<br />

Jordan Peterson, Jacob Hirsh (Psychology, University of<br />

Toronto, Toronto, ONTARIO Canada)<br />

Classic theories of action in the world are predicated on the assumption that objects exist,<br />

in some simple manner, and present themselves in that manner directly to perception.<br />

These objects are then evaluated, cognitively and emotionally, and action calculated, as a<br />

consequence of such evaluation. The emergence of the frame problem, a consequence of the<br />

extreme but previously unrealized complexity of the world, poses a fatal threat to those classic<br />

theories, as does the problem of combinatorial explosion, which manifests itself as the<br />

apparent impossibility of calculating the consequences of actions over extended timeframes.<br />

The world has to be simplified radically before it can be perceived, or before actions can be<br />

successfully implemented. Some of this simplification exists as a consequence of external<br />

structure. The artifacts of human culture protect individuals from much of the complexity of<br />

the world. Social being performs a similar role, as specialized and cooperative individuals can<br />

solve different sub-elements of the frame problem independently. Embodiment also plays a<br />

role. The manner in which the human body is constructed enables certain kinds of perceptions<br />

and actions, and makes others difficult, if not impossible. The psychological consequences of<br />

embodiment also play an important limiting and enabling role. Human individuals confront<br />

the world with an array of fundamental motivations, many of which are a direct consequence<br />

of hypothalamic function. The hypothalamus frames perception, projects to motor systems,<br />

and modulates autonomic responses, governing hunger, thirst, sexual responsivity, aggression,<br />

and exploration, among other primordial motivations and values. The emotional systems<br />

of the brain, governing approach and withdrawal, operate within those frames, in an<br />

essentially cybernetic manner, informing the organism directed by hypothalamic prompting<br />

whether perception, cognition, and goal-directed action is resulting in the consequences that<br />

are currently desired. Higher order cortical centers regulate the interaction between different<br />

hypothalamic value systems, organizing those intrapsychically and socially, so that each<br />

fundamental necessity can be successfully achieved, in the social world. Thus, the archaic and<br />

deeply physiological brain centers that human beings share with other animals, far down the<br />

evolutionary hierarchy, unconsciously structure our conscious phenomenological worlds. P8<br />

151 Finding the Function of Default States Adrienne Prettyman, Stephen Biggs<br />

(Philosophy, University of Toronto, Toronto, Canada)<br />

Brain scans show that subjects who lay awake and still without being given a task enter a<br />

particular type of brain state, which is commonly called the ‘default state’. Evidence suggests<br />

that the default state includes a structured network of brain regions that are, perhaps surprisingly,<br />

more active in the absence than in the presence of a task. Raichle et al. (2001; 2009)<br />

suggest that default states are particularly important to neuroscience because in the default<br />

state the brain is ‘active but not activated’, and thus, the default state can be used as a neurological<br />

baseline. Morcom et al. (2007) counter that since little is known about the cognitive<br />

function of the default state, these claims are premature. Adjudicating this dispute has proven<br />

to be difficult: since default activity occurs in the absence of a task, one cannot investigate<br />

the default state by presenting subjects with a task, but presenting subjects with tasks and<br />

observing their subsequent brain activity is the standard method for assessing the function of<br />

brain networks. So, given standard methods in cognitive neuroscience, we have reached an

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!