30.08.2015 Views

CONSCIOUSNESS

Download - Center for Consciousness Studies - University of Arizona

Download - Center for Consciousness Studies - University of Arizona

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

90 1. Philosophy<br />

space, information integration, attended mid-level representation....), and neurobiological<br />

theories (local reentrant, thalamo-cortical loop, synchronous oscillatory.....). Although most<br />

of these theories are developed and defended in isolation, there are open questions about the<br />

degree to which they might be successfully combined. Some combinations are obviously<br />

contradictory but others might be jointly accepted. At a minimum this might be a matter of<br />

mere consistency among pairs or larger groups of theories. However, there are cases in which<br />

diverse theories can be combined in complementary or mutually supportive ways. Such combinations<br />

might occur in at least three ways: 1. Different theories many describe consciousness<br />

at different levels of organization, and a lower level theory may describe processes or<br />

mechanisms that implement those at a higher level. This may occur within a given domain,<br />

e.g. a lower level of cognitive processing implementing a higher level of cognitive processing<br />

or across domains as with a neurobiological process providing the substrate for a cognitive<br />

model of consciousness.) 2. Different theories may describe distinct and separate aspects of<br />

consciousness, each of which needs to be included in a comprehensive account (a bit like “the<br />

blind men and the elephant”). These parts or aspects of consciousness may divide at different<br />

scales: at the very macro level, e.g. the supposed distinction between access consciousness<br />

and phenomenal consciousness, or at more micro levels - e.g. the distinction between conscious<br />

and unconscious processing may apply differently with respect to memory than it does<br />

with respect to perception. 3. Two or more models of consciousness may describe what turn<br />

out to be mutually interdependent aspects of consciousness. Integrating the two theories (or<br />

models) in such a case may provide an important and useful reconceptualization of each. The<br />

union of the two may transform our understanding of each in a way that allows us to better see<br />

how they together contribute to the nature of consciousness. I will provide a quick overview<br />

or “map” of some of the leading philosophical, cognitive and neurobiological theories/models<br />

of consciousness. I will then briefly survey some of the major prospects for integration among<br />

them with regard to each of the three types listed above. I will then focus on one particularly<br />

promising possibility for integration. That option aims to transformatively combine the reflexive<br />

view of consciousness as a form of self-awareness (whether higher-order or same-order)<br />

with global integration accounts. Both prior theories undergo a significant reconceptualization<br />

in the process of integration. The integrated account also provides an explanatory link<br />

between access and phenomenal consciousness, and deepens the connections to various proposed<br />

neural susbtrates. PL9<br />

102 The Phenomenal Element Benjamin D. Young <br />

(Philosophy, City University of New York, Graduate Center, New York, NY)<br />

Olfactory consciousness suggests a new theory of qualitative consciousness, which can<br />

predict the epistemic explanatory gap (Levine, 1983, 1993) without regress to a metaphysical<br />

gap (Kripke, 1980; Chalmers, 1996; Jackson 1982, 1986, 1993; Chalmers & Jackson, 2001).<br />

To demonstrate this conclusion the paper defends three key claims. First, it is argued that<br />

we smell objects. The olfactory object is identified as the chemical structure of molecular<br />

compounds or mixtures within odor clouds. The molecular structure itself is responsible for<br />

the quality of smell, which suggests that we smell matter. Second, based on research of blind<br />

smell (Schwartz, 1994, 2000; Sobel, 1999), mate selection (Wilson & Stevenson, 2006), and<br />

selection of social acquaintances (Li, et al., 2007), it is argued that qualitative consciousness<br />

within the olfactory system arises at the sensory level. Third, the content of our olfactory experiences<br />

is nonconceptual. Evidence for this claim derives from the properties of molecular<br />

compounds (Earley, 2005, 2007), the mechanism olfactory transduction (Friedrich & Laurent,<br />

2001; Schaefer, 2007), our psychological ability to recognize odorants within a complex odor<br />

(Laing, 1998; Livermore and Laing, 1998), and our ability to track olfactory objects (Porter<br />

et al., 2005, 2007), which all suggest that olfaction employs a combinatorial and functionally<br />

compositional system of representation (van Gelder, 1994; Young, 2003) that does not obey<br />

classical concatenative compositionality (Fodor, 1981, 1987; Fodor & Pylyshyn 1988; Fodor<br />

& McLaughlin 1990). The consequences of accepting these three claims are a new understanding<br />

of consciousness and the qualitative nature of our experiences. While the quality of<br />

smell is inherent to a chemical object, we can only know what it smells like and gain access to

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!