30.08.2015 Views

CONSCIOUSNESS

Download - Center for Consciousness Studies - University of Arizona

Download - Center for Consciousness Studies - University of Arizona

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

1. Philosophy 41<br />

conflict was primarily over the disagreement between Shen Xiu of the North who taught that<br />

enlightenment was a gradual process and Hui Neng of the South who taught that enlightenment<br />

was sudden and instantaneous. Certain critical Zen historians have downplayed this<br />

issue and argued that the split was due more to politics and personal ambitions. This paper<br />

argues that the conflict was based on opposing definitions of both consciousness and enlightenment<br />

which were only alluded to by the recorded gradual verses sudden enlightenment<br />

debate. The Northern school believed that consciousness was an objective, quantifiable and<br />

even malleable entity to be trained and molded. Their definition of enlightenment was the total<br />

purification of consciousness that took place over time. The Southern school headed by Hui<br />

Neng, believed that consciousness was a subjective, unquantifiable experience. They believed<br />

that enlightenment was achieved by the utter dissolution of all preconceptions, which in turn<br />

led to an experience of complete, unmitigated self awareness. As many modern discussions<br />

over consciousness involve extrapolations from primary and secondary sources concerning<br />

Zen Buddhism, this historical debate is very important to contemporary discussions over the<br />

nature of consciousness; for this medieval disagreement lies at the root of all subsequent<br />

views of consciousness found within the Zen tradition. This paper takes an in depth look at<br />

the both primary and secondary sources regarding the portrayal of consciousness during the<br />

golden age of Zen, paying special attention to differing descriptions of consciousness, definitions<br />

of enlightenment and meditative practices as taught by these two competing schools.<br />

The purpose of this paper is to shed light onto the historical backdrop upon which our contemporary<br />

discussions over the nature of consciousness are built and to both clarify and stimulate<br />

further scholarship on Zen’s notion of consciousness. C14<br />

3 The Detectable Consciousness Joy CY Hung, Allen Houng <br />

(Institute of Philosophy of Mind and Cognition, National Yang Ming University, Taipei,<br />

Taiwan)<br />

Ned Block pointed out that consciousness is a mongrel concept which involves a number<br />

of very different ‘consciousnesses’. Thus he made a distinction, the phenomenal-consciousness<br />

and the access-consciousness, among all the concepts connoted and the different phenomena<br />

denoted to avoid conflation which leads to bad results. Per his definition, the phenomenal-consciousness<br />

is experience; the phenomenally conscious aspect of a state is what<br />

it is like to be in that state. The access-consciousness is availability for use in reasoning and<br />

rationally guiding speech and action. Block further specified that whatever cognitive processes<br />

underlie our ability to report the experiences are to be defined as phenomenal consciousness.<br />

This definition might preclude some states that are defined conscious clinically, such as<br />

MCS (minimally conscious state). Patients of MCS demonstrate inconsistent but discernible<br />

evidence of consciousness by the index of N100, showing patients being able to detect the<br />

occurrence of discrete environmental sounds, and by the elicitation of MMN (mismatch negativity),<br />

showing patients being able to discriminate between different types of sounds. Recent<br />

studies show that the self-referential stimulus (call subject’s own name) effectively evokes<br />

residual brain activity by eliciting MMN in patients with disorders of consciousness (DOC)<br />

(Qin, 2008). These evidences imply their ability to create and utilize neuronal representations<br />

of the immediate sensory auditory environment (Näätänen, 1992; Näätänen et al., 2007) and<br />

thus are to be considered included within the realm of consciousness further to the phenomenal-consciousness<br />

defined by Block. We suggest a distinctive category, the detectable consciousness,<br />

to define conscious states that are unreportable, nevertheless can be detected by<br />

using ‘indirect’ techniques and objective measurement. The distinction could make clear the<br />

definition of conscious states related to this sort apart from the hard problems that are to be<br />

solved or might be unsolvable. This nuanced view will also make clearer the sphere of related<br />

researches on comatose state, dream state, memory, and mental imagery etc. C17<br />

4 What is it Like to be Unconscious? Gary Williams <br />

(Baton Rouge, LA)<br />

In this paper I want to respond to Ned Block’s claim that it is simply ‘ridiculous’ to suppose<br />

that consciousness is a cultural construction. In so doing, I will argue that a distinc-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!