30.08.2015 Views

CONSCIOUSNESS

Download - Center for Consciousness Studies - University of Arizona

Download - Center for Consciousness Studies - University of Arizona

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

80 1. Philosophy<br />

a picture, whereas the paradigmatic example of a discursive is a sentence. Of course, Fodor’s<br />

concern lies not with representations in general, but with mental representations, and he offers<br />

empirical evidence that people enjoy mental representations of both sorts. Fodor suggests that<br />

mental states such as thoughts are discursive, whereas states of, for example, mental imagery<br />

are iconic. Since Fodor believes mental icons are ipso facto unconceptualized, he thereby<br />

presents a spirited defense of the existence of what is known as non-conceptual content. Fodor<br />

claims that what cleaves the distinction between icons and discursives is the fact that discursives<br />

have what he calls canonical decompositions, whereas icons do not. Fodor acknowledges<br />

that both icons and discursives are compositional insofar as the structure and semantic<br />

properties of the wholes are dependent on the structure and semantic properties of the parts.<br />

However, Fodor maintains that what marks the difference between them is the way in which<br />

the parts of these representations compose. Since icons lack canonical decompositions, they<br />

thereby lack structure and so are unrestricted in the ways in which their parts compose. By<br />

contrast, discursives have canonical decompositions and hence have structure, and thereby are<br />

restricted in the ways in which their parts compose. My main aim in this paper is to challenge<br />

Fodor’s way of drawing distinction between icons and discursives. I remain (mostly) neutral<br />

about whether there is non-conceptual content, and I do not even dispute that there may be a<br />

distinction between discursives and icons. But, whether or not a distinction can be drawn, I do<br />

not think that we can draw it the way Fodor does. After briefly discussing Fodor’s program in<br />

general and his way of drawing the distinction, I turn to some reasons to think that icons are<br />

structured. In short, I argue that Fodor conditions for being an icon are at once too permissive<br />

and too restrictive. Fodor’s account entails that few or none of the things that we traditionally<br />

take to be icons, such as pictures, are iconic and that all sorts of things we do not take to be<br />

representations, such as footprints, are icons. I then catalogue several extant accounts of pictorial<br />

representation. I suggest that, on any of these plausible theories, icons are structured and<br />

I proffer a way to understand the sense in which icons have canonical decompositions. I then<br />

briefly discuss some empirical evidence that all mental representations, even at the earliest<br />

stages of visual processing, have structure. In closing, I critique Fodor’s reasons for thinking<br />

there are unstructured mental icons in the first place, and question the utility for Fodor’s<br />

theory in general of admitting unstructured icons into our mental ontology. I conclude we are<br />

thus better off thinking that Fodor’s condition for iconicity should be rejected. P1<br />

81 What is an Unconscious Mental State? Berit Brogaard <br />

(Philosophy, University of Missouri, St. Louis, St. Louis, MO)<br />

Conscious mental states have phenomenal character. There is something it is like to be<br />

in them. Having phenomenal character is sufficient for mentality. Furthermore, having a representational<br />

phenomenal character is sufficient for having intentional content. Unconscious<br />

states do not have phenomenal character. Yet intuitively some unconscious processes are (or<br />

correlate with) intentional mental states, for instance, dorsal stream processes and the residual<br />

visual processes responsible for blindsight. Here I consider and reject four candidate accounts<br />

of unconscious intentional mental states: dispositionalism, interpretivism, functionalism and<br />

potentialism. Dispositionalism treats the dispositions of individuals to behave or feel or think<br />

in certain ways as constitutive of mental states. However, this view has severe drawbacks. It<br />

misclassifies states that merely mimic states grounded in the right sort of underlying realizer.<br />

Interpretivism takes an unconscious state to be an intentional mental state just in case an ideal<br />

interpreter would judge that this is so. This sort of account encounters the same sorts of difficulties<br />

as dispositionalism when an individual’s behavior is not grounded in the right sort of<br />

underlying realizer. Functionalism does better in this respect. Though functionalism takes an<br />

unconscious state to be an intentional mental state just in case the state satisfies a certain prespecified<br />

role, the specification of the role can involve specifications of properties of underlying<br />

realizers. However, because functionalism does not require that unconscious mental states<br />

are adequately connected to phenomenal consciousness, it predicts that unconscious states<br />

that evidently are not states of the mind are mental states. Potentialism holds that an unconscious<br />

state is a state that has the potential to become conscious. However, on its most natural<br />

rendition, this view is implausible, as unconscious intentional mental states do not have the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!