30.08.2015 Views

CONSCIOUSNESS

Download - Center for Consciousness Studies - University of Arizona

Download - Center for Consciousness Studies - University of Arizona

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

62 1. Philosophy<br />

*is* the subject in whom phenomenal states are unified. All interactions in the mind have two<br />

sides: they entail both phenomenal experience *and* a physical causal role. Physical causal<br />

closure is maintained because the mind is a non-material entity with physical attributes, whose<br />

structures can act causally on neural processes. The domain of what constitutes “the physical”<br />

must necessarily be expanded. P7<br />

46 Identifying the Most Likely Explanation of Consciousness (Part 1): IBM and The<br />

SCALP Method Colin Morrison (Philosophy, Independent Researcher,<br />

Fife, Scotland, UK, Cupar, Fife United Kingdom)<br />

In this paper I propose that the proliferation of diverse and often incompatible views<br />

on consciousness in the philosophical literature is due largely to the fact that philosophers<br />

tend to be influenced by their intuitions when deciding which position to subscribe to, and<br />

I argue that this situation is extremely unsatisfactory. There are three main reasons for this:<br />

Firstly, it is clear from the history of science that human intuitions are not a reliable guide to<br />

a successful scientific explanation. Popular hypotheses have all too frequently been shown<br />

by experiment to be inadequate, and our explanations for things seem to have become ‘more<br />

and more unreasonable and more and more intuitively far from obvious’ (Richard Feynman<br />

1965). Secondly, our best explanation for the origin of our intuitions, Darwinian evolution,<br />

gives us no reason to think they would make the most likely position on consciousness seem<br />

most likely to us. And thirdly, the private nature of subjective experience makes it unlikely<br />

that the results of experiments will ever be sufficient to rule out all wrong intuitions on this<br />

subject. For those reasons it is argued that whether a particular position on consciousness feels<br />

likely or not ought to be regarded as COMPLETELY IRRELEVANT when assessing whether<br />

or not that position is the most reasonable one. Instead, it is proposed that this assessment be<br />

based purely on fully justifiable estimates of the probability of that position (and of each alternative<br />

hypothesis) being true. Although our inability to justify inductive inference appears<br />

to prevent us from calculating the probability that a hypothesis is absolutely true, I believe I<br />

have successfully developed a method of approximating the probability that a hypothesis is<br />

true given that certain well-supported scientific theories are correct. My proposal (dubbed<br />

‘inference from the best methodology’) requires that for each hypothesis on consciousness a<br />

general method of generating explanations for things be constructed that will not only yield<br />

the hypothesis in question when applied to the facts about consciousness, but will also (when<br />

applied to other facts) provide explanations for many phenomena for which well-supported<br />

scientific explanations are available. The probability that the hypothesis on consciousness<br />

is correct can then be approximated as the relative frequency at which that method, when<br />

applied to phenomena that have a reasonable number of features in common with consciousness,<br />

provides explanations that agree with the scientific explanations of those phenomena.<br />

Consequently, it is argued that the only way to construct a theory of consciousness that could<br />

be justifiably called “its most likely explanation” is by insisting that every aspect of that<br />

theory be determined by (or determinable from) a method of generating explanations that can<br />

be shown to provide ‘scientifically correct’ explanations for sufficiently relevant phenomena<br />

more often than can be achieved by any suitable alternative method. A proposal (dubbed ‘the<br />

SCALP method’ or ‘SCALPEL’) for that most successful method of generating explanations<br />

is developed and justified in this paper, and in a follow-up paper a theory of consciousness<br />

generated by that proposal is obtained. P1<br />

47 The Hard Problem of Concepts IS the Problem of Experience Joel Parthemore<br />

(School of Informatics, University of Sussex, Brighton, East Sussex<br />

United Kingdom)<br />

In theories of concepts, many attempts have been made to treat concepts as first, abilities,<br />

and only second, representations; as first basic (first-order) and only second, higher-order; as<br />

first private, and only second, public (or vice versa). The reason why none of these strategies<br />

works is, at heart, the same, and the same as the one Chalmer addresses in his ‘95 paper: the<br />

problem of experience and its enduring habit of mixing the seemingly objective (e.g., when<br />

we both measure the length of a certain stick, we get the same result, and we assume that,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!