30.08.2015 Views

CONSCIOUSNESS

Download - Center for Consciousness Studies - University of Arizona

Download - Center for Consciousness Studies - University of Arizona

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

86 1. Philosophy<br />

experience supervenes on its (supposed) extended vehicle (namely, the brain coupled with the<br />

(skilled active) body coupled with the environment). It is obviously required that this expected<br />

account should be coherent with the theory, and thus that it does not attribute to the brain<br />

features that would ultimately be compatible with the (rejected) assumption that the brain<br />

could be the sole or the main realizer of perceptual experience. The main arguments and the<br />

structure of this talk are as follows: (1) I first argue that there is currently only one available<br />

model of brain activity that is coherent with these vehicle-externalist theories of perceptual<br />

experience. It can be found in Humberto Maturana and Francisco Varela’s biological theory<br />

of operational closure and autopoiesis (Maturana and Varela, 1980; see also Thompson 2007).<br />

In this model, the nervous system is defined as a closed network of neuronal interactions,<br />

themselves generated by the network. It is an autonomous dynamical system which maintains<br />

the coherence of its own activity. It is organized by the operational closure of a network of<br />

reciprocally related sub-networks giving rise to sets of coherent activity. Its role is to couple<br />

movements with a stream of sensory modulations in a circular fashion, and thus to control the<br />

sensori-motor cycle of the organism in order to ensure its living character. It compensates for<br />

the perturbations and breakdowns of the ongoing perceptual-motor life of the organism. The<br />

sensori-motor coupling between the organism and the environment (coupling on which conscious<br />

experience is supposed to (partially) supervene) modulates and constrains the activity<br />

of the nervous system, which mediates and coordinates this sensori-motor coupling. (2) This<br />

model of neural activity is clearly non-representationalist. That is, it assumes that the activity<br />

of the brain cannot and does not need to include the manufacture, retrieval and use of mental<br />

representations of the environment or of the body. (3) Therefore, if vehicle-externalist theories<br />

of conscious experience endorsed this model of neural activity in order to answer to the (basic)<br />

question ‘what is the brain doing in your theory of perceptual experience?’ (the plausibility<br />

of this hypothesis is high, since these theories have to answer to this basic question, and<br />

that this model is currently the only available coherent answer), they would necessarily accept<br />

a non-representationalist strategy for describing both their explanans and explanandum.<br />

I conclude by examining whether these theories are able to endorse non-representationalism<br />

with coherence, and by assessing the prospects and consequences of such an endorsement,<br />

especially the following points: (a) what would the consequences of non-representationalism<br />

be for an explanation of the nature of the (non-phenomenal) contents of ‘bodily disengaged’<br />

experience (as we can find them in reflexive or monitoring consciousness for instance)?; (b)<br />

Does this non-representationalism amount to a denial of the intentional character of perceptual<br />

experience? P7<br />

93 Seeing Things Outside the Head Leopold Stubenberg <br />

(Philosophy, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN)<br />

According to Bertrand Russell, common accounts of vision are deeply mysterious. There<br />

are two problems. The first is a version of the hard problem of consciousness: how can a<br />

chain of purely physical events give rise to a visual experience? The second has to do with the<br />

remarkable saltatory (C.D. Broad’s term) power of vision-its ability “to leap the spatial gap<br />

between the percipient’s body and a remote region of space.” How can the visual experience<br />

that exists in me make me visually aware of an object that exists outside of me? My visual<br />

experience is the last link in a long causal chain that started at the external object. How can the<br />

last link of this causal chain make me aware of its first link? How does this visual experience<br />

make me perceptually aware of an object that is causally and spatially remote from itself and<br />

myself? Russell has interesting things to say about the first problem. But this talk is about the<br />

second problem. Direct realist theories of perception as well as intentional or representational<br />

theories of perception appear to address this issue head on. Direct realism introduces a perceptual<br />

relation-such as appearing or acquaintance-that is supposed to bridge the gap between the<br />

perceiver and her object. Russell himself subscribed to an acquaintance view for some time,<br />

but ultimately abandoned it. Intentional or representational theories are also often represented<br />

as addressing the problem by appealing to the special relation-the intentional relation. According<br />

to this view, my visual state is directed at, or is a representation of, or is about the object<br />

I perceive. I get at the remote object by representing it. But the nature of this “relation” as

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!