19.03.2013 Views

PoPulationand Public HealtH etHics

PoPulationand Public HealtH etHics

PoPulationand Public HealtH etHics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

It would be ideal to<br />

get active informed<br />

consent from parents<br />

if it would be feasible<br />

to do so without overly<br />

compromising results.<br />

research<br />

stigmatization harms that result from the surveillance. To<br />

help ensure this, monitoring of stigmatization resulting<br />

from the surveillance could be combined with the surveillance<br />

activity. In what follows, I assume that the expected<br />

benefits of the surveillance activity will outweigh expected<br />

harms (though this does warrant further empirical study)<br />

and, therefore, that conducting such surveillance is, inprinciple,<br />

justifiable. This then raises questions about the<br />

conditions under which surveillance should occur.<br />

Research vs. surveillance<br />

If the study described by Dilworth et al. were considered ordinary medical<br />

research, then active informed consent of children’s parents would arguably<br />

be required in light of research ethics “informed consent” requirements, and<br />

action would presumably be taken in cases where children are found to have<br />

BMIs that are problematic in light of research ethics “standards of care” requirements.<br />

2 In the surveillance program described, however, consent would<br />

be passive (i.e., “opt-out”) and parents will not be notified in cases where children<br />

are found to be “at risk.”<br />

This raises the following difficult questions: (1) What is the distinction between<br />

research and surveillance? and (2) What, if any, are morally relevant differences<br />

between research and surveillance such that the ethical requirements<br />

regarding the latter should be weaker than those regarding the former? We<br />

would need to answer both of these questions before concluding that the study<br />

under consideration is not subject to standard research ethics requirements.<br />

According to the us Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC), the<br />

distinguishing feature of research is the “purpose . . . to generate or contribute<br />

to generalizable knowledge”; the distinguishing feature of (relevant) non-research<br />

such as surveillance is the “purpose . . . to prevent or control disease or<br />

injury and improve health”. 3 There are numerous reasons why this technical<br />

distinction might be considered problematic. First, purposes — i.e., intentions<br />

— are notoriously difficult to verify, and so a distinction based on purposes<br />

seems a problematic way of determining whether a study is research or not.<br />

Second, it would appear that, by this definition, much prototypical research<br />

(i.e., clinical experimentation) might be considered non-research because it<br />

PoPulation anD <strong>Public</strong> <strong>HealtH</strong> <strong>etHics</strong><br />

28

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!