19.03.2013 Views

PoPulationand Public HealtH etHics

PoPulationand Public HealtH etHics

PoPulationand Public HealtH etHics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

certainly nothing in the ‘Millian’ paradigm that prevents<br />

seeing harm in this way. Indeed, a plausible view about<br />

harm is that we ought to define it as that which negatively<br />

affects our interests. 4 Given the risks to health resulting<br />

from exposure to smoke, it seems logical to see smoking<br />

in public itself as being such a potential harm, through<br />

its potential impact on others.<br />

Third, restrictions on outdoor smoking can be supported<br />

by the idea that this is the next natural step in the gradual<br />

changing of norms relating to smoking in society. The idea<br />

is that we want smoking to be seen as something that is<br />

unacceptable, as this is the best way to help smokers give up. This, in turn,<br />

makes it less likely that children grow up thinking of smoking as normal behaviour,<br />

thus decreasing the likelihood that they will, in turn, become smokers<br />

themselves. Such a view rejects the idea that it should always be liberty that<br />

takes priority as a value in cases of dispute with other values (such as harm<br />

prevention). Where we have good evidence about a potential harm, and we<br />

can reduce the chances of such a harm occurring, it is perfectly legitimate<br />

for a government to take action to seek to improve citizens’ health. If people<br />

strongly object, within a democratic society, the government is, ultimately,<br />

constrained by facing the public at an election.<br />

Fourth, while it is, indeed, the case that the traditional ‘Millian’ picture<br />

suggests that action motivated to bring about beneficial outcomes for competent<br />

individuals against their will is paternalistic, and therefore morally<br />

wrong, this argument is not so straightforward when applied to public health<br />

measures targeted at whole populations. 5 For example, such public health<br />

interventions do not aim (at least, directly) at individual benefit. Indeed, perhaps<br />

the benefit can only exist as a result of focusing on the population (not<br />

individual good at all). Likewise, if the justification of a policy for tobacco<br />

restriction is through an appeal to justice, it would seem incoherent to argue<br />

that this end could not be pursued because it was ‘paternalistic.’<br />

2. The ‘Stigma and Injustice’ argument<br />

The second argument in the case appeals to the idea that restricting smoking<br />

in outdoor places will increase stigma for already marginalised groups, and<br />

Equitable Consequences?<br />

67<br />

Where we have good<br />

evidence about a<br />

potential harm, and<br />

we can reduce the<br />

chances of such a<br />

harm occurring, it is<br />

perfectly legitimate<br />

for a government to<br />

take action to seek<br />

to improve citizens’<br />

health.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!