19.03.2013 Views

PoPulationand Public HealtH etHics

PoPulationand Public HealtH etHics

PoPulationand Public HealtH etHics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

policy<br />

through outdoor smoking, any legal restriction of such behaviour is morally<br />

wrong. The second argument, let us call it the ‘Stigma and Injustice’ argument,<br />

is that the intervention is likely to increase injustice, through the production<br />

of additional stigma towards minority groups in society that already<br />

suffer from disadvantage. The worry is that we know that members of such<br />

groups are more likely to smoke, and so this will have a differentially negative<br />

impact upon them. Both of these arguments, however, are problematic.<br />

1. The ‘Harm to Others’ argument<br />

There are a number of potential objections that might be raised to the argument<br />

that it is wrong to ban ‘outdoor’ public smoking based on the harm<br />

it might, or might not, cause to others. First, we might doubt whether it is<br />

really true that there is no evidence of potential harm to others. Can we assume<br />

that the issue is different if we distinguish outside space from inside<br />

space? Presumably, the relevant difference is supposed to be that smoking in<br />

an outdoor space is much less likely to affect in a negative way other peoples’<br />

health, because smoke rises into the ‘fresh air.’ However, it is surely unlikely<br />

that smoke will rise straight up into the atmosphere rather than, say, be blown<br />

towards the next group of persons on a crowded beach. The very fact you can<br />

smell your neighbours’ smoking on the next picnic bench suggests this is too<br />

simple. If so, then all of the substantial evidence we have about harm from<br />

smoking is relevant (especially the evidence about the benefits from reduced<br />

smoking in public places). 3 It does indeed seem intuitively true that there is<br />

likely to be less impact than if smoking occurred in a<br />

The very fact you can<br />

smell your neighbours’<br />

smoking on the next<br />

picnic bench suggests<br />

this is too simple.<br />

confined space. However, it does not follow from this<br />

that it is, therefore, safe. Given that the general negative<br />

health risks from smoking are well known and<br />

clearly established, the burden of proof should not rest<br />

with those seeking to restrict smoking. After all, we<br />

are talking about smoking in public places, even if it is<br />

outside, not restrictions on smoking in private spaces.<br />

Second, the notion of ‘harm’ should not be interpreted too narrowly. The presumption<br />

in the case seems to be that only direct physical harm to others<br />

will count as harm. Yet there are other harms as well. If it is more likely that<br />

others will continue smoking or current non-smokers will begin smoking if<br />

they are surrounded by smokers, might this not constitute a harm? There is<br />

PoPulation anD <strong>Public</strong> <strong>HealtH</strong> <strong>etHics</strong><br />

66

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!