19.03.2013 Views

PoPulationand Public HealtH etHics

PoPulationand Public HealtH etHics

PoPulationand Public HealtH etHics

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

esearch<br />

participation, leading to a less representative sample and thus compromised<br />

results such as less accurate prevalence estimates. The ultimate concern appears<br />

to be that this would have untoward effects on public health. Active<br />

informed consent in research, however, may likewise sometimes lead to less<br />

representative samples, and thus compromised research results, and this<br />

can also have untoward effects on public health. Why can we live with such<br />

compromised results in research but not in surveillance?<br />

It should be noted that, in some kinds of research, such as epidemiological<br />

research, the usual requirement of informed consent is waived when risks to<br />

subjects are minimal and/or when it would be infeasible to conduct the study<br />

if (active) informed consent were required. In the case of childhood obesity<br />

surveillance, it would be ideal to get active informed consent from parents if<br />

it would be feasible to do so without overly compromising results (and thus<br />

public health benefits). This approach would both respect autonomy (in this<br />

case, of parents) and achieve the public health benefits of the surveillance.<br />

On the other hand, if there is good reason to believe that it would not be<br />

feasible to seek active informed consent and/or that this would lead to substantially<br />

compromised results, with a resultant negative impact on public<br />

health, and if the stigmatization risks discussed above truly are minor, then<br />

perhaps active informed consent is not necessary. The requirement of “opt<br />

out” consent would, in any case, at least allow parents who object to the surveillance<br />

study to refuse their children’s participation, thus substantially, if<br />

imperfectly, protecting the autonomy of parents. In light of the inclusion of<br />

this “opt out” consent requirement, the proposed obesity surveillance is not<br />

completely at odds with informed consent.<br />

Second, consider standards of care. If the obesity study in question were<br />

considered research, it would presumably be required that children who test<br />

positive for obesity and/or for risk factors for obesity would receive some<br />

kind of intervention, just as clinical research subjects diagnosed with disease<br />

(or risk factors) during clinical experimentation would be treated or receive<br />

guidance/counseling. In the proposed surveillance study, on the other hand,<br />

there will be no follow up; parents will not even be notified if their children’s<br />

BMIs are problematic. Dilworth et al. say that doing so would “arguably, be<br />

unethical.” Yet, assuming that it would be feasible for the investigators to at<br />

least notify parents in cases where children’s BMIs are at levels considered to<br />

be dangerous (and in need of intervention) according to standard diagnostic<br />

PoPulation anD <strong>Public</strong> <strong>HealtH</strong> <strong>etHics</strong><br />

30

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!