04.04.2013 Views

Psychology & Buddhism.pdf

Psychology & Buddhism.pdf

Psychology & Buddhism.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Gestalt <strong>Psychology</strong> and Mahayana <strong>Buddhism</strong><br />

sought to organize disparate Buddhist teachings into a comprehensive view.<br />

He addressed the nihilism of his age (Napper, 1989, p. 37) with commentaries<br />

that stressed valid perception and valid cognition, in ways that exposed him<br />

to criticism of reification (see Dreyfus, 1997; Hopkins, 1983; also Dalai Lama<br />

XIV, 1993, p. 99). It would appear to be most difficult to do justice to the<br />

staggering dimensions of the Mahayana deconstruction of apparent reality, while<br />

likewise recognizing the human capacity for valid thought and perception, even<br />

though the task of overcoming ignorance inevitably demands, and thus implies,<br />

such intellectual and moral capacity, and its perfectibility. Gestalt theory may<br />

ultimately face the same tension of demands, whose seeming conflict nears the<br />

realm of paradox.<br />

Thus, while the basic principles of Gestalt psychology echo Madhyamika<br />

teaching, some critical implications of its message of relationality may have been<br />

left unexplored. Perhaps as a result Gestalt theory has been hard-pressed to<br />

account for those frequent situations, mentioned earlier, in which the relational<br />

determination of meaning is not a matter of conscious insight – where it is substantially<br />

overlooked in favor of absolutist thinking. Thus while Asch acknowledges<br />

the human tendency to restrict relational thinking and to succumb to an<br />

absolutization of social knowledge, he largely passes on the question of why and<br />

how this occurs (1952, p. 442, but see p. 631). Recall also Duncker’s observation<br />

of the tendency for value terms to succumb to reification as they become linked<br />

with static external behaviors. When circumstances change and those behaviors<br />

appear less fitting, the value itself – torn from its earlier context – may be disparaged.<br />

In the process, relativism gains a measure of face validity. Just why this<br />

kind of “cognitive freezing” (cf. Lewin, 1947) happens, or how it jibes with the<br />

relationality thesis, Duncker does not explain.<br />

<strong>Buddhism</strong> may help shed light on these problems. From the Madhyamika<br />

point of view, Gestalt theory may have defined the object of negation too<br />

narrowly, and thus overlooked subtler levels of reification binding the relational<br />

structure, the gestalt itself, such it may appear to exist independently. After all,<br />

relational understanding is not an all-or-none proposition. The awareness of<br />

fitting relations that gives rise to a gestalt, which permits its perceptual or conceptual<br />

discrimination, and grants it truth-value up to a point, need not reflect<br />

the full extent of its relationality. Where further relational determination goes<br />

unrecognized – where it remains unconscious – the result may be a measure of<br />

absolutization. This absolutization of meaning and value may be needed for a<br />

time in the development of individual and social consciousness (see Neumann,<br />

1969), but its benefits do not come without eventual costs, among them, alienation<br />

and enmity.<br />

Thus while both Gestalt and Madhyamika accept a relational determination<br />

of value, Madhyamika further radicalizes the Gestalt message of relational understanding<br />

by extending it to subtler layers of reification that the Gestalt critique<br />

91

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!