04.04.2013 Views

Psychology & Buddhism.pdf

Psychology & Buddhism.pdf

Psychology & Buddhism.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

92 Edward S. Ragsdale<br />

may not yet have penetrated. Consider naive realism. While Gestalt theorists have<br />

viewed it as an inevitable, albeit flawed, aspect of common thought, Madhyamika<br />

challenges us to let go of all manner of reification it entails. In raising the bar in<br />

this way, Madhyamika may help clarify the absolutizing tendencies that Gestalt<br />

theorists must acknowledge in their otherwise relational accounts.<br />

Consider that the Gestalt rejection of absolutism and relativism in favor of<br />

relationality was based largely upon comparisons across absolutist viewpoints,<br />

that is, analysis by Duncker and Asch of contrasts in traditional cultural beliefs<br />

and values. These absolutist valuations evince relational determination in exposing<br />

the fitting relation between values and underlying meanings, and likewise<br />

between meanings and their context of beliefs and perceptions. Yet they still<br />

reflect significant absolutization, most clearly manifested in their clinging to their<br />

own specific meanings, which are reified and clung to as absolute truths. This<br />

absolutization of situated values – this attribution of absolute, context-free truth<br />

to culture-bound expressions, returns us to where we began, to the cross-cultural<br />

conflicts that emerge across those encrusted forms, where value differences may<br />

appear absolute.<br />

This absolutization of meaning and value may involve, in Gestalt terms,<br />

insufficient insight into the contexts that govern their relational determination.<br />

Where meanings are shaped by contextual conditions that are effectively outside<br />

of awareness, the merely relational existence of those meanings is obscured, and<br />

they acquire a false sense of absoluteness. What is missing is insight into the basis<br />

of the meanings, that is, more penetrating awareness of their relational determinants,<br />

the contingencies both within and without the boundaries of the object,<br />

upon which its existence and meaning depend. If these bases were more accessible<br />

to consciousness, then the truth claims that proceed from them would be subject<br />

to critical examination, and meanings not fully attuned to their own relational<br />

basis might need to be modified, along with the valuations they support. This of<br />

course is what happens as layers of naive realism are seen through. One’s understanding<br />

of the object is revised as properties previously attributed to it alone are<br />

discovered to be relational facts, dependent in part upon an experiencing person.<br />

Thus conscious contexts may shape and support meanings, but within a constricted<br />

cultural universe that may have trouble seeing beyond itself to substantiate<br />

its own claims. This should come as no surprise. Cultural meanings are not<br />

necessarily assimilated purely on the basis of open-minded appraisal of their<br />

objective merits, or intelligent analysis of the truth-values of underlying beliefs.<br />

Nor does weak justification necessarily diminish one’s emotional investment in<br />

them. There may be other demands at work besides those following from open<br />

appraisal of sensibility. We are all pressed to make sense of our world, regardless<br />

of our variable capacity to do so accurately. Born into human cultures with little<br />

initial understanding of how things work, we take much on faith. We embrace<br />

meanings partly because they are underwritten by the groups that we at least

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!