04.04.2013 Views

Psychology & Buddhism.pdf

Psychology & Buddhism.pdf

Psychology & Buddhism.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

80 Edward S. Ragsdale<br />

identical with its parts, since self would thus become a mere redundancy, utterly<br />

synonymous with its parts (e.g., mind and body), with no meaning aside from<br />

them (see Hopkins, 1987, p. 264). Also, as in the previous example, if self and<br />

aggregates were identical, there would be many selves. Here my nose is myself,<br />

my arm is myself, my leg is myself, my mind is myself, and I become an incredibly<br />

vast number of selves. Imagine that each part is “I,” and as Hopkins suggests,<br />

try to figure out which “I” is to answer the door (1987, p. 266). Besides this is<br />

the problem that the proposition, in claiming an identity of whole and part, is<br />

bidirectional: Not only is my ear claimed to be myself, but myself is claimed to<br />

be my ear, in which case it becomes harder to assert that it is my eye.<br />

The problem is redoubled when we consider the temporal continuity of<br />

“real” selfhood, to try to see how the self at one moment, subject to laws of cause<br />

and effect, and prone to change, is identical with the self of another moment. Is<br />

the self of yesterday, or the self at one’s birth, or – if you will – the self of a former<br />

birth, truly the same as the self of today, or tomorrow? To say yes is to affirm<br />

a truly permanent self, incapable of change, and for that matter incapable of<br />

encounter or relationship, nor able to sow seeds or bear fruit of the law of karma.<br />

Satisfying ourselves that the self is not utterly the same as its parts, we ask<br />

if it is utterly different. We find that it is as hard to assert utter difference as it is<br />

to assert utter identity. There is no self that we can find that is observable separate<br />

from its parts. Moreover, says Nagarjuna, if self and its aggregates were altogether<br />

different, self “would not have the character of the aggregates” (as cited in<br />

Hopkins, 1987, p. 272). Yet self does have the character of the parts that compose<br />

it. It has the characteristics of the mind and body. Selves do what minds and<br />

bodies do. We cannot find a self apart from its parts, any more than we can find<br />

a self as identical to its parts.<br />

This deconstruction of the object of negation demands successful navigation<br />

past the Scylla and Charybdis of “extremist” views. If we define the object (of<br />

negation) too narrowly, we may negate too little, and remain trapped in the illusion<br />

of absolute existence. Defining it too broadly, we may succumb to the even greater<br />

danger of nihilism: We may negate too much and deny absolutely the conventional<br />

world, including the sentient beings we aim to help (see also Napper, 1989).<br />

Here it is critically important to realize that this unfindability of things calls<br />

into question their inherent, or intrinsic, or independent existence. It exposes our<br />

mistaken reification of apparent reality, in which we superimpose a sense of<br />

absolute existence onto things that exist only relationally. It does not deny conventional<br />

reality, that is, the authentic existence of things as dependent upon<br />

causes and conditions beyond themselves – though our reifying minds can abide<br />

only so much veridicality. Thus the conventional truth of things is also a “concealer<br />

truth.” It hides authentic reality behind false appearances (see Hopkins,<br />

1983, pp. 400–421). Yet as the illusion of independent existence is overcome,<br />

it eventually becomes possible to have valid cognition and valid perception

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!