13.06.2013 Views

Volume 19, 2007 - Brown University

Volume 19, 2007 - Brown University

Volume 19, 2007 - Brown University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Fluency and Fear 29<br />

Whereas Plato approaches rhetoric from a philosophical point of view,<br />

Thucydides encounters rhetoric as an historical condition. In his History of the<br />

Peloponnesian War, he chronicles several instances of rhetoric and its uses,<br />

most notably in Pericles’ funeral oration. While in this speech Thucydides<br />

presents an almost elegiac adoration for the tradition of Athenian oratory, there<br />

are several instances in his History where Thucydides notes different views of<br />

rhetoric. The most vigorous complaint against rhetoric is voiced by Cleon in the<br />

Mytilenian Debate. Cleon accuses the Athenian polity of favoring speech over<br />

action, becoming “victims of your own pleasure in listening and. . . more like an<br />

audience sitting at the feet of a professional lecturer than a parliament discussing<br />

matters of state” (His.3.38). Like Socrates, Cleon also acknowledges that<br />

speeches are not necessarily venues for just action with regards to state affairs.<br />

In the Melian Dialogue, the conquered Melians raise an indirect criticism of<br />

rhetoric:<br />

Athenians: . . .the standard of justice depends on the equality of power to<br />

compel. . .<br />

Melians: Then in our view (since you force us to leave justice out of account<br />

and to confine ourselves to self-interest). . .in the case of all who fall into<br />

danger. . .such people should be allowed to use and to pofit by arguments that<br />

fall short of mathematical accuracy. (His.5.89-90)<br />

In connecting “the power to compel” with “argument,” the Melians suggest<br />

a strong relationship between the two. Like Medea, the Melians see the abilty to<br />

argue as critical to the “power to compel” others. Like Socrates, though, they<br />

acknowledge that such arguments do not necessarily leave room for truth or<br />

justice.<br />

However, the only complaints against rhetoric discussed thus far have been<br />

lodged by non-Athenians. Given that Thucydides was writing as an Athenian, he<br />

might actually be criticizing critiques of rhetoric. However, in the section of his<br />

History describing the end of Plataea, an Athenian presents the view that Medea<br />

and Socrates share, namely that: “[g]ood deeds do not require long statements;<br />

but when evil is done the whole art of oratory is employed as a screen for it”<br />

(His.3.67). While it is hard to discern whether Thucydides himself agrees with<br />

the various complaints the speakers raise in his History, when he attributes to<br />

Athenians and non-Athenians alike a shared distrust in rhetoric and oratory, he<br />

certainly acknowledges the ambivalent status of rhetoric within his society. On<br />

the one hand, powerful orators like Pericles serve as proud reminders of what<br />

Athens stands for, yet Athenians themselves note that words and rhetoric can be<br />

“a screen” for evil intentions.<br />

Euripides’ Medea, then, does show something about the Greeks to the<br />

Greeks, as Geertz would suggest. Among other values and attitudes certainly<br />

uncovered in his tragedy, Euripides simultaneously exposes and confirms the<br />

contradictory nature of rhetoric and the tension inherent in the very mode of<br />

communication that informed Athenian political, intellectual, and theatrical life.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!