22.07.2013 Views

I Chose Liberty - Ludwig von Mises Institute

I Chose Liberty - Ludwig von Mises Institute

I Chose Liberty - Ludwig von Mises Institute

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

110 I <strong>Chose</strong> <strong>Liberty</strong>: Autobiographies of Contemporary Libertarians<br />

In the interim I received a first class education in philosophy and sociology, with only a<br />

smattering of economics thrown in on the side. My most influential teachers were not<br />

particularly libertarian, but they were all hard-nosed. Ernest Nagel, the great philosopher<br />

of science, always defended common sense against its intellectual detractors, and taught me<br />

philosophy of law with the then new book The Concept of Law by H.L.A. Hart. David<br />

Sidorsky forced us to read Plato’s Thaeatetus, Descartes’s Mediations and G.E. Moore’s Ethics<br />

with real care. The last piqued my interest because I could not understand why anyone<br />

would care whether the good was a natural or nonnatural quality, but at least I became<br />

convinced, without really knowing why, that there had to be some connection between<br />

what was good, what was desirable and what was desired. Moore may not have had the right<br />

answers, but at least he had the right questions. And a dose of Sydney Morgenbesser on<br />

meta-ethics made it crystal clear that there was no easy going through the philosophical<br />

thicket. Arthur Danto was ingenious, but I thought always ultimately wrong because he<br />

preferred philosophical ingenuity to psychological information. And Daniel Bell, much my<br />

mentor, introduced me to sociology and political theory. His was a world of detail and<br />

nuance, but he did make it clear that, however Marx might have gone astray, he did understand<br />

at least one thing, namely, that there was no understanding politics without power.<br />

This last message packed real punch, because the cloistered discussions within Hamilton<br />

Hall were not immune from the massive political pressures that were slowly building up<br />

both before and after the Kennedy assassination. Those were heady times, with the civil<br />

rights movement in full swing and the terrible events of Vietnam beginning to unfold. No<br />

one could fail to think about the problems of race and war, and I can recall the strong sense<br />

of support for the civil rights act as a powerful antidote to the evils of segregation in the<br />

South. But I can still remember as a junior sitting in Alan Westin’s government class, as<br />

student after student praised the colorblind nature of the proposed civil rights law while<br />

one of my former Great Neck school mates, Stephen Kahan, protested in his high-pitched<br />

voice that the new laws were defective because they overlooked the public/private distinction<br />

that everyone assumed was either unintelligible or obsolete. It was that initial comment<br />

that planted the seed of doubt that later became a full frontal assault on the antidiscrimination<br />

laws as they applied to private employers in competitive markets. I have since come to<br />

believe that the public/private line does not cover the full front, and that the question of<br />

market structure—monopoly, practical or legal, versus competition—also counts. But those<br />

refinements came only after those initial doubts about the scope of public power, doubts<br />

which at that time were not informed by any political theory.<br />

That missing element of political theory came to me quite by accident at Oriel College,<br />

Oxford University where I studied law (for a degree no less) right after graduation from<br />

Columbia College. The Oxford legal education is quite different from the American, and<br />

at first blush it offered me little reason to expect that I should form a general world view<br />

while working in the stacks of the Oriel College library. The English had a narrow and<br />

constrained view of what constituted the proper subject of a legal education. In part this<br />

came because of the decisive division of power within the English framework, whereby the<br />

critical decisions were made in the Civil Service, away from the watchful eyes of judicial<br />

review. The bottom line, therefore, was that the development rights in the green belt around

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!