12.07.2015 Views

PACIFIC WORLD - The Institute of Buddhist Studies

PACIFIC WORLD - The Institute of Buddhist Studies

PACIFIC WORLD - The Institute of Buddhist Studies

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Book Reviews 305one regrets that these scattered observations do not evolve into a moresystematic critique.In the next section entitled “Prospectus,” Heisig puts the central part<strong>of</strong> the book in perspective. We find here in a summary format much <strong>of</strong> thecritical argumentation that was <strong>of</strong>ten only intimated before. <strong>The</strong> materialis excellent, making one wish Heisig had used it earlier where he couldhave developed it in more detail. “Prospectus” opens with an outstandingreview <strong>of</strong> the Kyoto School from several different angles. Heisig ranks theoriginality <strong>of</strong> the School fairly as below the greatest Western thinkers suchas Kant, Hegel, Nietzsche, James, and Heidegger. He also observes thatcompared with their contemporaries such as Whitehead, Wittgenstein,Foucault, Derrida, Habermas, and Gadamer, the Kyoto School “looks likesomething <strong>of</strong> an anachronism. What is more, a great many ideas in thephilosophical tradition out <strong>of</strong> which Nishida, Tanabe, and Nishitani workedhave been rejected” (p. 264; that last statement is tantalizing, for Heisigdoes not enlarge upon it anywhere in the book). Similarly, their contributionto the traditional <strong>Buddhist</strong> studies has been negligible. <strong>The</strong>ir originalitylies rather in “the appropriation <strong>of</strong> eastern ideas into western philosophy”(p. 260). Heisig notes that:Nishida, Tanabe, and Nishitani do not really belong to the history<strong>of</strong> philosophy as we know it and under the assumptions that havedominated it up until now. Unless one is prepared to dismiss out<strong>of</strong> hand the idea <strong>of</strong> opening up western philosophy to the standpoint<strong>of</strong> world philosophy, there is literally no place to locate theKyoto School properly. <strong>The</strong>y have positioned themselves in aplace as unfamiliar to the eastern mind as it is to the western.<strong>The</strong> question <strong>of</strong> locating them in effect questions the way wehave located philosophies east and west. In this context, theirsis not a derivative contribution but something original andrevolutionary (ibid.).Heisig <strong>of</strong>fers three good, although perhaps arbitrarily selected, suggestionsfor further research on the Kyoto School, by the same tokenpointing to the weaker spots <strong>of</strong> his own book: the relation between the threephilosophers, the connection between them and the historical transformations<strong>of</strong> the day, and the central role <strong>of</strong> individual experience that theSchool holds up as the standard <strong>of</strong> truth and the foundation <strong>of</strong> philosophy.<strong>The</strong> last two points are particularly important since the disastrous engagement<strong>of</strong> the three thinkers in wartime events shows “the limits <strong>of</strong> aphilosophy oriented to the contemplative” (p. 263). Heisig then singles outthree topics as the suitable criteria for evaluating the place <strong>of</strong> the KyotoSchool in the world philosophy (pp. 265–266). <strong>The</strong> first is their polyvalentnotion <strong>of</strong> no-self, combining the soteriological, moral, and metaphysical

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!