06.09.2021 Views

The Intelligent Troglodyte’s Guide to Plato’s Republic, 2016a

The Intelligent Troglodyte’s Guide to Plato’s Republic, 2016a

The Intelligent Troglodyte’s Guide to Plato’s Republic, 2016a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

25 Laughter and Lying<br />

See 388e-389d. Socrates’ next two recommendations are puzzling. <strong>The</strong> first<br />

suggests that “violent laughter” be avoided lest “a violent reaction” result. <strong>The</strong><br />

second suggests that permission <strong>to</strong> tell lies be denied <strong>to</strong> most citizens, but granted<br />

“as a form of drug” <strong>to</strong> the city’s rulers. With respect <strong>to</strong> the point about laughter,<br />

he may have in mind what he was saying at the end of Book II about gods being<br />

perfect and therefore incapable of change of any sort, including presumably<br />

violent changes of mood. On this interpretation, Socrates is thinking that the<br />

guardians should, ideally, be raised <strong>to</strong> be as godlike as possible, steady and<br />

decisive in their judgments and feelings. But he may also be intending <strong>to</strong> criticize<br />

and reject a particular kind of laughter – the callous sort that comes of unjustly<br />

ridiculing others. In the passage he quotes from the Iliad, the craft-god<br />

Hephaestus, who has a noticeable limp, is described as causing the other gods <strong>to</strong><br />

burst in<strong>to</strong> “unquenchable laughter.” To ridicule persons because of their physical<br />

handicaps is bad enough, but what is so particularly and grossly unjust in this case<br />

is that Hephaestus is doing his best <strong>to</strong> bring reconciliation and peace between Zeus<br />

and Hera, Zeus having just threatened <strong>to</strong> strangle her. Moreover, Hephaestus’<br />

limp, the trigger for all this laughter, was acquired as a result of his having been<br />

hurled <strong>to</strong> earth by Zeus the last time he rose <strong>to</strong> his mother’s defense (see Iliad,<br />

I.586-594). So what Socrates may be thinking is that <strong>to</strong> laugh in this way at such a<br />

person in such a situation is <strong>to</strong> lose one’s ethical bearings – something no god<br />

could ever do, and no guardian should ever do. With respect <strong>to</strong> the<br />

recommendation about giving permission <strong>to</strong> lie, this is puzzling because<br />

dishonesty seems inconsistent with justice. That rulers should be permitted <strong>to</strong> lie<br />

<strong>to</strong> enemies in ruse de guerre situations is one thing (see 382c), but how can it be<br />

just <strong>to</strong> deceive one’s fellow citizens? We will have occasion <strong>to</strong> consider what<br />

Socrates has in mind when he begins <strong>to</strong> offer examples, the first of which comes at<br />

the end of Book III. While it is not entirely clear at present <strong>to</strong> what extent he<br />

approves of the deliberate use of falsehoods, it is clear that for a falsehood <strong>to</strong> be<br />

acceptable it has <strong>to</strong> be properly authorized, and it has <strong>to</strong> be prescribed for the good<br />

of the city.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!