21.12.2013 Views

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

Hayek's The Constitution of Liberty - Institute of Economic Affairs

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

h ay e k ’ s t h e c o n s t i t u t i o n o f l i b e r t y<br />

r e q u i r e m e n t s o f t h e r u l e o f l aw<br />

True law is both general and equal<br />

Generality or abstractness is a necessary feature <strong>of</strong> law. Hayek<br />

had made this clear particularly by distinguishing in Chapter 10<br />

between laws and commands. A command is an order to someone<br />

to take a particular action or refrain from it; and it presupposes<br />

someone who has issued the command. A law, by contrast, ‘is<br />

directed to unknown people,’ and it speaks in an impersonal<br />

voice. It abstracts ‘from all particular circumstances <strong>of</strong> time and<br />

place’ and ‘refers only to such conditions as may occur anywhere<br />

and at any time.’ Hayek grants that these distinctions are not<br />

hard and fast, since laws ‘shade gradually into commands as their<br />

content becomes more specific’ (149–50).<br />

<strong>The</strong> principle <strong>of</strong> generality does not, however, encompass<br />

the requirement that ‘any law should apply equally to all.’ A law<br />

might be general and yet make different provisions for different<br />

classes <strong>of</strong> persons and, where classes are defined narrowly, implicitly<br />

favour specific individuals. Complete equality before the law<br />

means ‘that no attribute belonging to some individuals but not to<br />

others should alter their position under the law’ (1955: 36). Hayek<br />

insists that we should strive towards this goal, but grants that it ‘is<br />

probably both unattainable and undesirable’ (ibid.: 36). He does<br />

not object in principle to laws that single out a particular group,<br />

e.g. women, or the blind, or people above a certain age, so long as<br />

the legitimacy <strong>of</strong> the distinction is acknowledged by those inside<br />

the group as well as those outside it. Yet ideally, equality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

law aims to equally improve ‘the chances <strong>of</strong> yet unknown persons’<br />

and is ‘incompatible with benefiting or harming known persons<br />

in a predictable manner’ (209–10, 153–5).<br />

Hayek denies that justice is an attribute <strong>of</strong> law, independent<br />

<strong>of</strong> its generality, certainty and equality. If a law ‘confines itself to<br />

regulating the relations between different persons and does not<br />

interfere with the purely private concerns <strong>of</strong> an individual,’ we<br />

have no test for its compatibility with a reign <strong>of</strong> freedom ‘other<br />

than its generality and equality’ (210). Here, as in Chapter 6,<br />

Hayek interprets the principle <strong>of</strong> equality to mean that the law<br />

should treat people alike in spite <strong>of</strong> inequalities that arise from<br />

nature and from nurture. Equality before the law increases the<br />

de facto inequalities among individuals, but these are advantageous<br />

to a free society. Also, the Rule <strong>of</strong> Law is at odds with the<br />

quest for distributive justice. Those who pursue it ‘will in practice<br />

find themselves obstructed at every move by the rule <strong>of</strong> law.’<br />

Distributive justice requires government to decide what different<br />

individuals will receive or reward them according to someone’s<br />

conception <strong>of</strong> their merit. <strong>The</strong> Rule <strong>of</strong> Law demands, however,<br />

that individuals be treated equally under general laws, without<br />

regard to their particular qualities or circumstances (232).<br />

<strong>The</strong> laws consist <strong>of</strong> ‘general rules that apply equally to everybody.’<br />

It follows that those persons who enact and apply the laws<br />

must also be subject to them. This requirement – that the laws<br />

apply equally to those who govern as well as to any private person<br />

– reduces the risk that the state and its agents will act oppressively<br />

(210).<br />

<strong>The</strong> Rule <strong>of</strong> Law requires an independent judiciary<br />

Hayek hesitates to make the ‘separation <strong>of</strong> powers’ a blanket<br />

requirement <strong>of</strong> the Rule <strong>of</strong> Law, since this doctrine has a variety<br />

<strong>of</strong> meanings, some <strong>of</strong> which Hayek disapproves <strong>of</strong>. He does insist,<br />

however, that the judiciary should constitute ‘a separate power’<br />

from the legislature. <strong>The</strong> Rule <strong>of</strong> Law means that ‘the laying-down<br />

124<br />

125

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!